Emotion
Psychology began as a cognitive science, and problems of cognition have been at the forefront of psychological research and theory since the early 19th-century psychophysicists, such as Weber and Fechner, and the late-19th-century investigators of learning, such as Pavlov and Thorndike. As a result, we know a great deal about how cognitive processes operate. This understanding of cognition is the subject of the lectures on Learning, Sensation and Perception, Attention and Memory, and Thought and Language. It is also summarized in an overview of Cognitive Psychology.
But
cognition isn't all there is to the mind. As noted in the
Introduction, the 18th-century German philosopher Immanuel
Kant asserted (in his Critique of Judgment, 1790,
Introduction, Part 3) that:
"there are three irreducible faculties of mind: knowledge, feeling and desire.
Kant's three faculties of mind
constitute what E.R. Hilgard, an eminent 20th-century American
psychologist, called "the trilogy of mind":
- cognition,
- emotion, and
- motivation.
Kant thought that the three faculties were irreducible -- meaning, for example, that the principles of emotion couldn't be derived from the principles of cognition, and vice-versa. However, since the resurgence of interest in emotion and human motivation in the 1960s, a number of cognitive and social psychologists have argued that our feelings and desires are cognitive constructions -- that is, that they have their origins in our perceptions and interpretations of events. Put bluntly: you don't really feel angry, and you don't want a hamburger; you just believe that you do.
Cognitive constructivism is one important element in the psychology of emotion and motivation, but there are reasons to suspect that it is not the whole story. There are many psychologists these days who believe that there are important aspects of affect and conation that are substantially independent of cognition. For example, they argue that the brain systems that mediate emotion are different from those that mediate cognition.
For this reason, it seems best not to foreclose the matter of the relation between cognition and emotion. In this supplement, and in the complementary one on motivation, we will explore both the ways feelings and desires are shaped by cognition, and the ways in which they might have an existence independent of knowledge.
As noted in the Introduction, this stance means that psychology cannot be just a cognitive science, concerned with problems of knowledge and belief.It must also be an affective science, concerning with problems of feeling and emotion. And it must also be a conative science, concerned with problems of motivation and desire.
However, and for reasons that are not entirely clear, the emotional and motivational aspects of mental life have received much less attention from psychologists than the cognitive ones. As a result, especially since the "cognitive revolution" of the 1960s, every psychology department in the country, if not the world, has a well-developed program of research and graduate training in cognitive psychology, cognitive science, or cognitive neuroscience. But emotion and motivation have gotten much less attention -- sometimes only a course or two. Similarly, there are many textbooks on cognitive psychology, but very few devoted to emotion and motivation.
This situation is starting to change. This supplement, and the accompanying one on motivation, are intended to provide an introduction to the psychology -- better put, the psychologies -- of emotion and motivation.
The Vocabulary of Emotion
The problem for the psychology of emotion can be stated simply:
Why do people feel the way they do -- happy, sad, guilty, proud, whatever?
Psychologists often explain people's behavior in terms of their feelings.
Defining Emotion
First, what do we mean by an emotion? How does it differ from a sensation, or a memory?
Emotions have been defined as "brief,
multicomponent, largely automatic psychological mechanisms
that coordinate a variety of cognitive, physiological, and
motor processes, facilitating an adaptive response to
particular kinds of fitness-relevant opportunities or threats"
(Shiota et al., 2017). A more succinct definition of emotion
is as "brief, adaptive responses, involving physiological and
cognitive reaction to objects, people, or situations"
(Niedenthal et al., 2006). Yet another is as "A multicomponent
response to a challenge or opportunity that is important to an
individual's goals" (Oakley et al., 2006).
But, frankly, neither definition will do, because they don't do anything to distinguish emotional states from other mental states, like cognitive or motivational states. It's better, in my view, to define an emotion as an internal mental state consisting of various subjective feelings of pleasantness or unpleasantness.
Psychologists often make
further distinctions among affect, emotion, and
mood.
- Affect is generally pleasant or unpleasant.
- Emotions are more defined types of pleasantness or unpleasantness, such as happiness or surprise, sadness or anger or fear.
- They tend to be relatively high in intensity, accompanied by excitement and agitation.
- They are typically accompanied by physical feelings (our hearts race, we smile and laugh, our face flushes). Think of an emotion as subjective feeling accompanied by physiological arousal, plus behavior that expresses or copes with the emotional feeling state.
- Although there are exceptions, emotions tend to be about something: You're not just angry, you're angry because your girlfriend dumped you.
- Moods are pervasive, global feelings, with relatively low intensity.
Some psychologists use these terms interchangeably, and these Lecture Supplements will do this as well. But there are technical distinctions among these affective states, and we shouldn't forget about them.
Wilhelm Wundt, who was primarily
interested in the structure of sensory experience, turned his
attention to the problem of the structure of emotional
experience as well. He argued that any emotional experience
could be decomposed into three dimensions.
- Pleasantness vs. unpleasantness: Is it a good feeling or a bad feeling?
- Excitement vs. Calm.
- Strain vs. Relaxation.
The dimensions of excitement-calm and strain-relaxation proved controversial, but everybody accepted the basic distinction between pleasant and unpleasant emotional states.
But Wundt was onto something: there's more to the experience of emotion than a simple matter of feeling good or bad.
Many explorations of the structure of emotional experience begin with the assumption that the important emotions have been encoded in language. A survey of the dictionary by James Averill, for example, found at least 500 different words that refer to affective states. Of course, there are some redundancies among these words, and some words are more central to emotional experience than others. This raises the question:which emotion terms are basic?
The Psychometric Approach
The psychometric approach to this question subjects a representative set of mood adjectives to statistical analysis by techniques such as factor analysis to determine the relationships among them.
James Russell proposed that we need two
independent dimensions to account for the differences among
the various emotional states.
- The first of these, following Wundt's introspective analysis, was defined at the poles by positive vs. negative affect. Some emotional states are pleasant, others are unpleasant.
- The second dimension was defined by high vs. low arousal, similar to Wundt's dimension of calm vs. excitement.
Russell further found that the various emotional states demonstrate what is called a circumplex structure. A circumplex is a circular arrangement of objects such that the angular distance between them represents the correlation between them. That is, objects that are close together on the circumplex are very similar to each other, or very likely to co-occur.
But as intuitively appealing as the Russell circumplex is, it's not the only possibility.
When
Watson and Tellegen performed the same sort of analysis, they
also uncovered two orthogonal (independent) dimensions of
affect, but they named them quite differently.
- One dimension is defined by low vs. high positive affect.
- The other dimension was defined by low vs. high negative affect.
Watson and Tellegen argued that affects were descriptively bipolar -- that is, positive vs. negative -- but affectively unipolar -- that is, they are more or less positive, and more or less negative. Only the high end of each dimension represents emotional arousal. The low end reflects the relative absence of affective involvement.
This is the kind of dispute that causes fistfights at professional meetings, and which the rest of the world probably looks at scornfully, like medieval debates over how many angels can dance on the head of a pin. But, in fact, the dispute is important.
Consider, for example, the problem of how emotional states are generated by the brain. Given the neuroscientific doctrine of modularity, we can hypothesize that there is a specific brain module, or system, for generating emotions -- and, in fact, there might be separate modules for generating each distinct emotion. This is very likely to be true, but we'll never find those modules unless we know what we're looking for. If positive and negative affect lie on separate dimensions, but we do our brain-imaging studies based on the assumption that they lie on opposite ends of a single dimension, we'll never find the neural substrates of emotional life.
The fact of the matter is that The
Watson-Tellegen and Russell circumplexes are pretty much the
same. You can get the one simply by rotating the other by 45o.
But there are reasons for preferring the Watson-Tellegen
structure.
- Pure measures of positive and negative affect are actually uncorrelated with each other -- even when subjects rate their feelings "at the present moment". So it's possible to have positive and negative feelings simultaneously -- which wouldn't be possible if they were polar opposites.
- We'll see this situation again in the lectures on Psychological Development, where it turns out that masculinity and femininity -- which most people also view as polar opposites - -are actually independent of each other, so that an "androgynous" person can be high on both masculinity and femininity.
- Researchers have uncovered functional dissociations between positive and negative affect -- that is, variables that affect levels of positive affect (sorry) without also affecting negative affect (sorry again), and vice-versa. This strongly suggests that positive and negative affect should be represented independently of each other.
- For example, levels of negative affect are related to stress, poor coping responses, health complaints, and the frequency of unpleasant events. These variables are not related to levels of positive affect.
- And, similarly, levels of positive affect are related to social activity and satisfaction, and the frequency of pleasant events. But these variables are not related to levels of negative affect.
The Linguistic Approach
An alternative, linguistic approach to this question is based on studies of categorization.
Schwartz and Shaver, based on the revisionist "probabilistic" approach to categorization, began -- as did the psychometric approach -- by extracting a representative list of emotion terms from the dictionary. They then asked a group of subjects simply to sort them into categories based on perceived similarity.
A statistical method called cluster analysis (which is related to factor analysis, except that it yields discrete clusters of objects rather than continuous dimensions) yielded five basic categories of emotion.
- Love, including such terms as liking and passion.
- Happiness, including such words as joy and ecstasy.
- Anger, including such terms as frustration, rage, resentment, disgust, and envy.
- Sadness, including such words as agony, grief, disappointment, guilt, loneliness, and pity.
- Fear, including such words as alarm, fright, and anxiety.
Schwartz and Shaver also uncovered a sixth group,surprise, which they labeled a pre-emotion. They argued that surprise occurred in response to any violation of expectancy. Because surprise can be either positive or negative, they didn't label it as an emotion per se.
Schwartz and Shaver also collected narrative accounts of people emotional experiences (real or imaginary), and then coded these for spontaneous descriptions. Based on their results, they proposed that each emotional category was represented by a summary prototype that contained three different types of features:
- Antecedents of the emotional state.
- Responses to the emotional state (cognitive, somatic, behavioral).
- Attempts to control the emotions (for negative emotions only).
An Expanded Vocabulary of Emotion
Yet another way of identifying emotions is to
ask subjects to report on their emotional responses to various
stimuli. This was the approach taken by UC Berkeley's
Alan Cowen and Dacher Keltner (PNAS 2017), who asked
more than 850 men and women to rate their emotional responses
to more than 2,000 video clips. The subjects were
demographically diverse (recruited through Mechanical Turk),
and the videos were selected to elicit a wide variety of
emotional reactions.
- Some subjects freely described their emotional
reactions.
- Other subjects ranked each slip in terms of how strongly
it elicited each of 34 emotions.
- Still others rated each video in terms of 14
dimensions.
In the graphic below, each of the 2000+ video
clips is plotted in a two-dimensional space alongside other
clips that evoked similar emotional responses. For
example: Anxiety, Fear, Horror, and Disgust
lie close together, as do Sexual Desire and Romance,
but these categories are separated from each other by a
completely blank space. Admiration, Awe,
Joy, and Aesthetic Appreciation also lie close
together, and are clearly separated from the other two.
Look closely (click on the graphic to get a bigger image), and
you can see how this works out for the remaining emotional
states. In fact, you can go to an interactive
version of this graphic to view the corresponding
videos: simply hover over a selected video (note that some of
the videos have strong sexual or violent content).
Cowen and Keltner plausibly claim that their
study supports a much richer variety of emotional experiences
than had been implied by previous theories -- such as the
traditional affect circumplex. More substantively, their
study sheds new insight into what might be called the
architecture of emotion. These 27 emotional states are
organized into distinct clusters; within each cluster,
different emotions are related to each other along continuous
gradients of affective connotation.
Another line of research by Cowen and Keltner has focused on
oral expressions of emotion -- spontaneous vocalizations that
express our emotional state, like "Oooh!" and "Aha!"
(Cowen, Keltner, et al., Am. Psych. 2019).
They had listeners rate more than 2,000 "vocal bursts"
and found evidence for at least 24 distinct emotional
states. As in their earlier research on visual
expressions of emotion, these 24 emotions can be organized
into a multidimensional space in which the various emotions
are represented as points, and the distance between points
represents the similarity between the emotions they
represent. Link
to an interactive map of vocal emotion.
Whether the final number is 27, or 24, or something else,
emotion researchers have begun to expand the taxonomy of
emotions beyond the six "basic emotions" postulated by Ekman
and Friesen: anger, disgust, fear, happiness, surprise, and
sadness. They offer a further categorization of "new"
emotions -- that is, emotions that are new to emotion
researchers. These include:
- attachment-related emotions like love, desire, and
sympathy;
- self-conscious emotions like embarrassment, shame,
and pride;
- epistemological and self-transcendent emotions like awe, ecstasy, gratitude, interest, and confusion.
The Multiple-Systems View of Emotion
Although we often think of our
emotions as unified experiences, Peter Lang (1968) has
proposed that every emotional state actually consists of three
different components or systems.
- The verbal-cognitive component is the subjective experience of emotion, labeled and described by language -- for example, the feeling of happiness or fear.
- The overt motor component is the publicly observable expression of the emotional state -- such as smiling in the case of happiness, or escape or avoidance in the case of fear.
- The covert physiological component is the internal physiological correlate of the emotional state, such as various signs of autonomic arousal in the case of fear.
Ordinarily, these three components vary
together, especially when the emotion is fairly intense. But
there are circumstances in which these components can be in a
state of what Rachman and Hodgson called desynchrony.
For example, a person might not feel fear, even though he or
she may show signs of avoidance, or autonomic arousal.
Another multiple-systems view has been
proposed by UCB's Robert Levenson, who distinguishes among
three emotional functions:
- Generation of emotion (including, presumably, the three components delineated by Lang).
- Regulation of emotion, as when someone tries to control their facial expressions.
- Recognition of emotional expressions in other people.
Setting aside the idea that each
specific emotion -- fear, joy, anger, disgust, etc. -- might
be mediated by a separate brain system, producing the
characteristic patterns of physiological response that
accompany each emotion, the implication of Levenson's theory
is that each of these functions is also mediated by a
different brain system.
Individual Differences in Emotion
We think of the various emotions as mental states, episodes in our conscious mental lives, but there are also individual differences in emotionality. Some people seem to be happier than others, while others seem to be more fearful. It may also be that some people are simply disposed to experience positive or negative emotions. In that case, we can think of emotion as a more or less stable trait, as well as a discrete mental state.
Clinical Assessment of Emotion
For example, clinical psychologists often use questionnaires for the assessment of their patients' typical emotional states, such as the Beck Depression Inventory (BDI) , and the Taylor Manifest Anxiety Scale (MAS). The Hamilton Rating Scale of Depression (HAM-D) is frequently used to measure depression as a trait in clinical trials of antidepressant drugs.
As another example, the Spielberger State-Trait Anxiety Inventory (STAI) measures anxiety both as a state (subjects rate how anxious they are feeling right now, as they complete the questionnaire) and as a trait (subjects rate how anxious they feel in general).
Individual Differences in Emotionality
Based on their circumplex analysis of the structure of emotion, Watson and Tellegen created the Positive and Negative Affect Scales (PANAS) scales for the measurement of individual differences in emotionality. The PANAS consists of 10 mood adjectives for each scale. In a typical application, subjects rate (on a 1-4 scale) the frequency with which they have experienced each over a particular period of time. The time itself can vary from "right at the present moment" to "today, or over the past few days", "past few weeks", "past year", or "in general". Scores on the PANAS correlate highly with the two "superfactors" on the Multidimensional Personality Questionnaire (MPQ) a personality inventory, suggesting that positive and negative emotionality are core dimensions of individual differences in personality.
Another interesting dimension of emotionality is alexithymia, a term derived from the Greek meaning "no words for moods". Individuals who score high on alexithymia have a poor vocabulary for the expression of emotion, and an inability to distinguish among emotions. They may feel something, but they don't seem to know whether they feel bad or good, or whether they're angry or sad. They have low levels of emotional imagery, and little emotion in their fantasy lives. In terms of Lang's multi-component view of emotion, it seems like alexithymics are unable to connect two aspects of their emotional experience -- the visceral/somatic and the cognitive/evaluative -- a desynchrony between the verbal-cognitive and covert-physiological components of emotion. For these individuals, their emotional state is highly dependent on context.
Some clinical studies have suggested that alexithymia is a risk factor for certain psychophysiological disorders (to be discussed in the lectures on Psychopathology and Psychotherapy). But there is very little experimental literature on alexithymia to date.
Another clinically relevant dimension of emotionality is anhedonia, or the inability to experience positive emotion. Anhedonia is one of the classic symptoms of schizophrenia -- one of the "Four As", along with associative disturbance, ambivalence, and autism. But recent experimental studies suggest that anhedonia in schizophrenia may be misleading: schizophrenics may experience emotion, but just don't express it in their behavior. If so, that would count as another kind of desynchrony, this time between the verbal-cognitive and overt-motor components. Loren and Jean Chapman and their colleagues developed an Anhedonia Scale as part of their long-term attempt to identify individuals who are at risk for schizophrenia.
While anhedonia affects the experience or expression of positive emotions,repressive style is, essentially, the denial of negative emotion. Originally, repressive style was measured by Byrne's Repression-Sensitization Scale, but the R-SS turned out to be more of a measure of anxiety, or neuroticism, than of repression per se.
More recently, Weinberger
and his colleagues (1979) proposed an alternative technique
for the measurement of repressive tendencies, combining
Taylor's MAS with the Marlow-Crowne Social Desirability
Scale (SDS), which is a measure of defensiveness.
Weinberger and his colleagues then divide the distributions of
both scales at their medians, creating four groups of
subjects:
- True Low Anxious -- subjects with relatively low scores on both the MAS and the SDS.
- True High Anxious -- subjects with relatively high scores on the MAS and relatively low scores on the SDS -- subjects who feel anxious and don't mind admitting it.
- Probable Repressors -- subjects with relatively low scores on the MAS, but relatively high scores on the SDS, suggesting that they might be trying to hide their true level of anxiety.
- Defensive High Anxious -- subjects with high levels of both anxiety and defensiveness.
You see the logic. Weinberger then attempted to validate his classification by showing that, for example, Repressors behaved like True High Anxious subjects on various experimental tasks.
Later Weinberger introduced a more refined instrument for the assessment of repressive tendencies, but the logic of the assessment remains the same.
Theories of Emotion
OK, so now we have a better idea of what emotion is, and what the structure of emotional life might look like. But what are emotions really? Where do they come from? How do they play a role in our mental and behavioral economy?
The first thing to be said, along the lines of the Doctrine of Mentalism, is that emotions help determine our behavior. When we're happy we smile; when we're angry we lash out; when we're afraid we tremble and sweat and escape and avoid. Our behavior is caused by our emotions just as our behavior is caused by our beliefs and desires. One of the reasons we want to know how emotions work is that we recognize the role that emotion plays in our behavior.
The James-Lange Theory
That makes sense. But, in fact, one of the
earliest theories of emotion actually reversed the direction
of causality. In the late 19th century, William James, the
famous American philosopher and psychologist, and Carl Lange,
a famous Danish physician, physiologist, and psychologist,
independently proposed that the actual situation was the
reverse. For them, environmental events elicited some bodily
response, and that our perception of these efferent activities
is experienced as an emotion.
- James, in his 1884 paper, focused on responses of the whole body, especially those involving the skeletal nervous system. In his formulation, we don't run from the bear because we're afraid; rather, we're afraid of the bear because we run.
- Lange, in his 1885 paper, focused on visceral responses, especially those involving the autonomic nervous system. In his formulation, we don't shed tears because we're sad; we feel sad because we notice that we're shedding tears.
The theory is somewhat counterintuitive, because it reverses the usual direction of causation. Our emotions don't cause our bodily reaction to events; rather, our bodily reactions cause our emotions. Stated this way, the James-Lange theory appears to violate the Doctrine of Mentalism. On the other hand, perhaps appearances are deceiving. Except in the case of purely reflexive responses, there must be some initial perception and interpretation of the situation before we can respond to it. Perhaps, then our initial emotional state, resulting from our perception of the situation, influences our initial bodily response, and then feedback from our bodily response influences the intensity of our total emotional experience.
But let's set the issue of the temporal dynamics of emotion aside for now.
The big point, for now, is that regardless of whether it's James's focus on skeletal responses, or Lange's focus on visceral responses, the upshot of the James-Lange theory is that each emotional state is generated by, and thus correlated with, a specific pattern of nervous system activity.
And that's precisely where
critiques of the James-Lange theory weighed in. Walter B.
Cannon, a prominent American physiological psychologist,
weighed in with a five-point critique of the James-Lange
theory. Despite the vaunted position of William James in the
status hierarchy of American psychologists (and world-wide,
too, for that matter), Cannon's critique was widely considered
to be devastating to the James-Lange position.
- Cannon noted, first, that paraplegics can still experience emotion, even though their spinal cord has been severed from their brains -- thereby effectively preventing them from getting feedback from their skeletal musculature and viscera.
- And, as a matter of empirical fact, different emotions, such as fear and anger, do not seem to be associated with different patterns of bodily reaction.
- Along the same lines, our perception of our visceral responses to stimulation are very diffuse and nonspecific.
- Moreover, autonomic responses, at least, recruit more slowly than do emotional responses -- thus making it difficult for autonomic responses to cause emotional states.
- Finally, experimental manipulation of autonomic responses -- speeding up or slowing down the heart rate, for example - -didn't seem to alter subjects' emotions.
Note that most of these criticisms
apply more powerfully against Lange's version of the theory
than James's. This is because James emphasized motor feedback,
from the skeletal musculature. Cannon, a physiologist who
identified the role of the autonomic nervous system in the
"flight or fight", naturally focused on the ANS. Of course,
the evidence from paraplegia weight against James as well as
Lange, but it remained possible, at least in principle, that
the feedback in question came from the facial
musculature, which would be unaffected by spinal-cord injury.
We will return to this point later, in a discussion of
theories of emotion proposed by Silvan Tomkins, Paul Ekman,
and others.
Remember, from the lectures on "The Biological Bases of Mind and Behavior", that the complete formulation of "flight or fight" is freeze, flight, or fight, tend and befriend.
Cannon's critique led to the formulation of a general arousal theory of emotion by Duffy (1934), Lindsley (1951), Woodworth and Schlossberg (1958), and others. According to this theory, emotional states reflect a single, undifferentiated state of physiological arousal; the apparently qualitative differences among the various emotions (anger, fear, etc.) actually reflect quantitative differences in intensity levels.
But this resolution didn't satisfy everyone -- not least because introspection made it evident that there were qualitative differences among emotional states that were independent of arousal. Where do these come from?
Cognitive Appraisal Theories
One popular approach, proposed by Stanley
Schachter and Jerome L. Singer (1962), is that the different
emotional states were cognitive constructions. Schachter and
Singer agreed with Cannon, Duffy, and others that emotional
stimuli elicits a state of physiological arousal that is both
undifferentiated and unexplained. This state of arousal is
then interpreted by the actor -- an interpretation that is
shaped by information available in the current situational
context. Qualitatively different emotional states, then, are
produced by the cognitive evaluation of undifferentiated
arousal. The implication of the theory is that unexplained
arousal is affectively neutral.
Schachter and Singer supported this view with experimental evidence. In their study, they recruited subjects for an experiment on the effect of vitamins on task performance. The subjects were injected with a drug which they were told was a vitamin -- but which was really epinephrine, which increases physiological arousal. Some subjects were told about this side-effect of the drug, others were left uninformed. Half of the subjects in each group was then tested along with another subject, who was actually a confederate of the experimenter; the remaining subjects were tested alone. For some subjects, the confederate was instructed to behave in an angry manner, expressing hostility toward the experimenters, tearing up papers, and the like; for other subjects, the confederate was instructed to behave in a euphoric manner, giggling and playing with a hula-hoop. Then, among other tasks, the subjects provided ratings of their current mood. Among those subjects who were tested with the euphoric confederate, those who had been kept ignorant about the side-effects of the drug reported being in a more positive mood than those who were informed. Among those tested with the angry confederate, the ignorant subjects reported being in a less positive mood than the informed subjects. Thus, those subjects who had no other explanation for what they were feeling looked to their environment for clues: those who were in a euphoric environment felt happy, those who were in an angry environment did not.
The Schachter-Singer theory quickly became the conventional wisdom in social psychology. Which is interesting, because, if you look at the graph, the experimental evidence was pretty ambiguous. Still, the theory had some intuitive appeal, especially in the face of the apparent failure of alternative theories. And if you think about it, the Schachter-Singer theory actually is a variant on the James-Lange theory: we don't feel afraid because we perceive ourselves running from the bear, but because we perceive other people running from the bear; we don't feel sad because we notice that we're crying; we feel sad because we perceive that other people are crying.
The basic idea behind the Schachter-Singer theory was subsequently extended in a variety of ways, in a set of theories that all were predicated on the view that emotional states result from cognitive appraisals.
Lazarus
For example, Richard Lazarus (1966), a clinical psychologist, offered an alternative cognitive-appraisal theory that emerged from his practical interest in coping. From his point of view, emotions are not just things we experience. They are also experiences that we can cope with, and control, at least to some extent. Lazarus' view is linked to modern psychoanalytic theory, with its focus on stress, conflict, and other negative states. Freud argued that we attempted to cope with negative emotion by virtue of various defense mechanisms. Lazarus, on the other hand, argued that our coping strategies are largely conscious.
Lazarus began with the assumption that emotions, like the rest of life, have an adaptive function, which is to promote survival. Emotions supplement reflexes and physiological drives, in that they are less rigid: they have low stimulus specificity and high response flexibility. Virtually any stimulus can elicit virtually any emotion, depending on how it is appraised. And emotional appraisal concerns adaptive significance for the individual -- whether the stimulus is good or bad for one's own well being.Most important, Lazarus argued that emotions reflect the organism's appraisal of the environment in terms of harm and benefit, based on antecedent motives and beliefs.
Thus, for Lazarus, there
are three elements in emotion:
- cognitive appraisal;
- action tendency; and
- somatic reaction.
Lazarus further identified
the stages of cognitive appraisal:
- evaluation with respect to well-being;
- evaluation with respect to coping resources;
- evaluation with respect to cognitive and behavioral options;
- and, finally, a re-appraisal after some response has been engaged.
And there are two types
of appraisal with quite different sets of consequences:
- Benign appraisal can lead to:
- Automatic coping with the stimulus, without emotion;
- Transformation of the threat into something positive;
- Genuine positive emotions, including positive emotions that result from the mastery of danger.
- Threat appraisal can lead to:
- Negative emotion, followed by direct action to deal with the threat;
- Benign re-appraisal.
Whether benign or threatening, appraisals of events are always in terms of the relationship between the person and his or her environment.A core relational theme summarizes the person's relationship to the environment in terms of cost and benefit.The person-environment relationship can be described either at a molar level (which provides an economical summary of the relationship) or at a molecular level (as in detailed questions and answers about the relationship. Regardless of the level, each core relational theme produces a distinct emotion.
Mandler
If emotions reflect our appraisals of the
circumstances under which we become aroused, then where does
arousal come from? George Mandler (1975, 1984), a cognitive
psychologist who (naturally) was an early and ardent advocate
of the Schachter-Singer theory, distinguished between two
broad positions on emotion.
- What he called the fundamentalist position, rooted in Darwin, emphasized a small number of innate emotional responses that occur more or less reflexively (or, perhaps better, instinctively) in response to appropriate stimuli.
- Counterposed to this was the constructivist position, rooted in William James, that proposes that there is a potentially infinite number of different emotional responses, depending on how the person perceives his or her bodily activity (the part emphasized by James and Lange) and the context in which it occurs (emphasized by Schachter and Singer).
Mandler's unique contribution to the development of cognitive appraisal theories of emotion was to focus on the arousal component. Recall that Schachter and Singer assumed that subjects experienced an undifferentiated state of physiological arousal, which they then interpreted in terms of the context in which it occurred. In the Schachter-Singer experiment, the arousal was induced artificially, by giving subjects an injection of epinephrine. But how do we get emotionally aroused in the real world outside the laboratory?
Mandler proposed that physiological arousal results from the occurrence of a perceptual/cognitive discrepancy: we become aroused whenever our expectations are violated, our intentions are frustrated, or our habitual behaviors disrupted. This state of arousal is, as in the Schachter-Singer theory, undifferentiated with respect to the stimulus situation. The arousal, in turn, elicits attentional activity, as the subject scans the environment to determine the cause of the discrepancy. Once the source has been determined, the arousal state is interpreted by the actor -- an interpretation that is shaped by the current situational context. Thus, our emotional states are doubly shaped by cognitive evaluations -- first, of the source of the discrepancy; and second, of the context in which arousal occurred.
Smith & Ellsworth
Building on Lazarus' work,
Craig Smith and Phoebe Ellsworth (1983) proposed a more
elaborate cognitive-appraisal theory of emotion itself (Smith
was a student of Lazarus' at Berkeley; Ellsworth began
collaborating with Smith when she was a graduate student at
Stanford). Like Lazarus, they placed great emphasis on the
valuation component of emotion. They assumed that emotional
experience is linked to the person's appraisal of the
environment, and attempted to characterize the various
appraisals that gave rise to particular emotions.
Note, that while assumed that emotional experience is related to one's appraisal of the environment, they did not assume that emotions were pure cognitive constructions. They admitted that, as in the James-Lange theory, there may be different patterns of bodily response associated with different emotions. But they focused their theory on the perceptions of bodily change, in context, in an attempt to capture the cognitive differences among various emotions.
In the original statement of their theory, Smith and Ellsworth (1985) argued that cognitive appraisal proceeded in terms of six different dimensions:
- Pleasantness of the experience, an evaluative dimension that gives feelings their positive or negative valence.
- Anticipated Effort -- whether the person must do something, or do nothing, in response to the emotion-eliciting event.
- Certainty, or the predictability of the consequences of the event.
- Attentional Activity, or the extent of cognitive focus on the event and its consequences.
- Attributional Activity -- judgments of whether the event is under situational control (as opposed to being the result of human agency); and if the event is the product of human agency, whether the responsible agent is oneself or some other person.
To
illustrate the application of this scheme to exemplar
emotions, consider the distinction between happiness and
pride:
- Pleasantness: both states involve pleasant rather than unpleasant feelings.
- Anticipated Effort: both involve relatively little cognitive effort.
- Certainty: for both states, the consequences of the eliciting event are highly predictable.
- Attentional Activity: both entail a strong desire to pay attention to the stimulus (not to mention the state!).
- Attributional Activity: In pride, there is a clear attribution of human control, especially self-control (we take pride in things that people have done, and especially in things that we have done ourselves); in happiness, by contrast, Smith and Ellsworth think that there is less attributional activity of any kind -- we just sit back and enjoy it.
Although emphasizing the
importance of cognitive appraisals, Smith and Ellsworth do not
assume that emotions are merely cognitive constructions. They
allow that there might be different patterns of bodily
response associated with the various emotions.
- For example, facial expressions might be correlated with various components of emotion:
- A frown, with unpleasantness or anticipated effort.
- Raised eyebrows with attention to the environment.
- Lowered eyelids might reflect an attempt to shut out the environment.
- Raising or lowering the corners of the mouth might also be associated with pleasantness or unpleasantness.
In this way, patterns of facial expressions, associated with each emotion, would be predictable from the components of appraisal.
Similarly, autonomic activity might reflect anticipated effort (autonomic arousal).
Note that in these examples the physiological patterns reflect the person's appraisal of the situation. They may contribute to the emotional experience in some way, but they are effects of appraisal, not independent causes of the emotion. Moreover, facial expressions (at least) serve to communicate the individual's appraisal, and convey information about his emotional state to other people. Finally, the bodily activity may reflect the person's preparation for coping activity, rather than the emotion per se.
A more recent version of
the theory, proposed by Smith and Lazarus (1990),
distinguishes between two different kinds of appraisal.
- Primary appraisal concerns the motivational relevance of the event being appraised. Does it involve one's personal goals and concerns?
- If not, then there is no emotional response.
- If it is congruent with goals and concerns, then the emotion is positive.
- If it is incongruent, then the emotion is negative.
- Secondary appraisal has to do with accountability: Who receives credit or blame for the harm or benefit that will result from the event? Secondary appraisal proceeds along several different dimensions.
- The problem-focused coping potential has to do with the individual's ability to act directly on the situation -- to manage the situation so as to satisfy goals and concerns or avoid threat or harm.
- The emotion-focused coping potential has to do with the individual's ability to regulate his or her emotional state, especially in the face of threat or harm.
- Future expectancy has to do with the possibility of changing an unpleasant situation so as to make it motivationally congruent.
So, as in the original
theory, there are different appraisal patterns for specific
emotions, involving the core relational theme and the various
components of primary and secondary appraisal, all of which
are focused on the adaptive function of emotion. To
illustrate, consider the patterns of appraisal associated with
various emotional states.
- Anger occurs when someone someone else is to blame for some negative outcome.
- The event is motivationally relevant, but also motivationally incongruent.
- Someone else is accountable, not oneself.
- The adaptive goal is to remove the source of the harm, or to undo the harm that has been done.
- Guilt occurs when oneself is to blame for some negative outcome.
- The event is also motivationally relevant and incongruent.
- Oneself is accountable.
- The goal is to make reparations, and promote responsible behavior.
- Fear and anxiety occur in response to ambiguous dangers and threats.
- The event is motivationally relevant and incongruent.
- Emotion-based coping potential is low or uncertain.
- The goal is to avoid potential harm.
- Sadness occurs in response to irrevocable loss.
- The event is motivationally relevant and incongruent.
- There is low problem-focused coping potential.
- There is low future expectancy.
- The goal is to get help and support, and to disengage from the loss.
- Hope occurs when there is some possibility of success or amelioration of some threat or loss.
- The event is motivationally relevant and incongruent.
- There are high expectations for the future.
- The goal is to sustain commitment and coping.
- Challenge occurs in the context of optimism, or potential for success.
- The event is motivationally relevant and incongruent.
- Coping potential is high.
- Future expectancy is high.
- The goal is to sustain or motivate mastery.
- Happiness occurs in the context of actual success.
- The event is motivationally relevant and congruent.
- The goal is to reward success.
- Interest occurs when the event is personally relevant.
- The event is motivationally relevant, but it may be congruent or incongruent.
- The goal is to direct and sustain attention to the event.
Clore & Ortony
An alternative cognitive-appraisal theory of emotion was proposed by Clore and Ortony (1988), who focused on the antecedents of emotional state. They observed that different emotions arise in different situations, and that the events that trigger emotions occur in the context of different goal states.
Clore and Ortony began by trying to define emotions -- by distinguishing between emotional and non-emotional feelings. For this purpose, they devised six linguistic tests. For example, they asked subjects to fit each candidate term into various sentence frames, such as Jane felt _____ or Although at that moment Jane was _____, she was emotionally content. Note that while a non-emotion word like bored fits both frames (you can be both bored and content), an emotion word like embarrassed does not.
On the basis of their
linguistic tests, Clore and Ortony divided the lexicon of
affective states into 6 categories:
- Responses to Other-Actions such as appreciated, and neglected.
- Body-States such as drowsy and tired.
- Cognitive States such as bored and interested.
- Pure Traits such as superstitious and materialistic.
- Pure Emotions such as embarrassed and jubilant.
- Trait Emotion Hybrids such as anxious and proud.
Next, Clore and Ortony
attempted to determine the role of cognition in each emotional
state. Beginning with the assumption and cognition and emotion
are closely related.
- In the first place, they argued that emotions arise from a person's appraisal of the motivational relevance of events to his or her plans and goals.
- And in the second place, emotions reflect the cognitive value of that goal - -that is, the proximity of the relevant goal to the person's highest-level goals; the number of goals that are affected by the event; and whether the event facilitates or interferes with the goal.
Thus, distinct emotions are determined by the different ways that events and goals can be related.
Accordingly, they grouped
emotional states into five different categories, depending on
the goal state, triggering conditions, and determinants of
intensity.
- Hedonic group: Some emotions, both positive and negative, are experienced as one is making progress toward, or moving away from, one's goals.
- Emotions in the hedonic group further involve a focus either on the emotional state, or on the goal object.
- Examples of hedonic emotions include pleased, and displeased, as well as pleased-with and displeased-with.
- State Anticipation group: These emotions involve the expectation of positive or negative outcomes -- plus, just to complicate things, when an outcome is unanticipated.
- and also whether the realized state is positive or negative.
- Examples include disappointment, hope, satisfaction, shock, surprise, worst fears confirmed, fear, and relief.
- Quality of Action group: These emotions depend on
whether the valence of action is positive or negative,
- and also on the identity of the human agent: self vs.
other as agent, and self as actor vs. other as
experiencer of the outcome.
- Examples include pride, anger at self, admiration, contempt, gratitude, and anger.
- Standards group: These emotions depend on whether
the actor is the self or some other person, whether the
standard of evaluation is public or private, and whether
the person exceeds some standard, or violates it. Examples
of emotions associated with exceeding standards are pride
and admiration.
- Examples of emotions associated with violating standards are unease, shame, remorse, embarrassment, indignation, contempt, anger ,guilt, disgust with self, revulsion, and disgust.
- Loss group: These emotions occur when the self is the experiencer of the loss of a concrete or abstract object; they also occur when some other person experiences loss, and differ depending on whether the self or other is the actor responsible for the loss.
- The loss of a concrete object can be permanent or impermanent, and the object lost can either be another person, or some impersonal object.
- The lost abstract object can be the esteem of others, self-esteem, choice or opportunity, or a skill.
- Examples include
- pity (when the other is both the actor and
the experiencer);
- shame (when the self is the actor and the
other is the experiencer);
- grief (in response to the permanent loss of a specific other person);
- pining (in response to the temporary loss of a specific other person);
- homesickness (from the temporary loss of an impersonal object ;
- feeling betrayed results from the loss of
others' esteem;
- and shame results from the loss of self-esteem.
To see how this framework
works, consider the emotion of happiness:
- There is a focus on events rather than on agents or objects.
- If we change the focus to the agent, we no longer feel happiness: rather, we feel something like approval.
- If we change the focus to the object, we no longer feel approval, but rather something like liking.
- Happiness is elicited by desirable rather than undesirable events (obviously).
- If we change the event to undesirable, we no longer feel happy, but rather feel unhappy.
- In any case, the intensity of our emotional state increases with the desirability or undesirability of the eliciting event.
In a further development
of their theory, Clore and Ortony (1990) described three
components of the phenomenal experience of emotion:
- The cognitive/interpretive component involves construing an event in terms of the person's goals and aspirations, standards and values, and tastes and attitudes.
- The motivational/behavioral component includes the desires and behaviors resulting from this construal.
- The physiological component reflects both of the other components.
They also argued that
the three different bases for construal yielded three, not
five, major classes of emotions:
- Goal-based emotions are based on the desirability of events.
- Positive examples include relief and happiness.
- Negative examples include unhappiness, depression, frustration and disappointment.
- Standard-based emotions are based on the approval of one's actions.
- Positive examples include pride and admiration.
- Negative examples include anger, embarrassment, and disenchantment.
- Attitude-based emotions are based on one's liking of objects.
- Positive examples include liking.
- Negative examples include disliking.
- In addition, there may be compounds of goal- and standard-based emotions, that depend on both the action of some agent and the associated event.
Johnson-Laird and Oatley
Yet another cognitive theory of emotion was proposed by Johnson-Laird and Oatley (1987, 1988, 1989), two cognitive scientists. It's an interesting theory, but by now you've got a good sense of what cognitive theories of emotion look like, and that's all that matters.
Facial Expressions of Emotion
Cognitive-evaluation theories dominated research on emotion in the 1960s and 1970s, but came to be challenged by a resurgent psychobiological view.
To some extent, this turn
of affairs was stimulated by a reconsideration of the role of
the face in emotion. Recall that one of Cannon's criticisms of
the James-Lange theory was that paraplegic individuals, who
could receive no afferent impulses from their skeletal
musculature, could nonetheless experience emotions. That
seemed to rule out James's emphasis on the perception of
muscular activity. Lange's emphasis on the perception of
visceral activity, moreover, was ruled out by Cannon's other
critical points. But Cannon's critique left open the role of
the facial musculature.
- We express our emotional responses on the face.
- Feedback from the facial musculature is mediated by cranial nerves that do not feed through the spinal cord.
- Therefore, James might be right after all, provided that what is perceived is the activity of our facial muscles.
In fact, a formal
facial-feedback hypothesis of emotion was offered by
Schlossberg (1952), and more prominently by Silvan Tomkins
(1962). Tomkins argued that facial expressions of emotion
could be classified along three dimensions:
- Pleasantness vs. Unpleasantness;
- Rejection vs. Attention;
- Activation vs. Tension Relaxation.
Tomkins proposed that there were certain primary emotions triggered by innate neural programs -- and thus do not require any particularly "cognitive" appraisal. In his view, certain classes of environmental stimuli automatically activated these innate neural programs, which generated a display of emotion on the face. This display served primarily to communicate one's emotional state to other people. But Tomkins also proposed, in line with the James-Lange theory (or at least James's version of it) that feedback from the facial expression generated the subjective experience of emotion.
Tomkins' theory, in turn, was based on
research on the evolution of emotional expression -- a topic
that began with one of Charles Darwin's last works, The
Expression of the Emotions in Men and Animals(1872). In
this book, as its title implies, Darwin documented a number of
similarities between the expression of emotion in humans, and
in non-human animals -- particularly, though not exclusively
mammals. Nonhuman animals, of course, do not have the ability
to express their emotional states through language. They have
to do it through facial expressions and other bodily gestures,
posture, and gait. Humans have a capacity for verbal language,
of course, but in Darwin's view we retained a capacity for nonverbal
communication of our emotional states, as part of our
evolutionary heritage.
Note that Darwin discussed evolutionary continuities in the nonverbal expression of emotion. The implication is that the emotional response came first, and then it was expressed on the face and elsewhere. This is the standard view of emotion, and consistent with the Doctrine of Mentalism. Tomkins added the idea that feedback from the face could generate, or at least amplify, the emotional state itself. To some extent this reverses the direction of causality, consistent with the James-Lange theory.
Paul Ekman, a
student of Tomkins, picked up on Darwin's arguments concerning
evolutionary continuity. He proposed that there are certain basic
emotions that are part of our evolutionary heritage and,
thus, shared with other primates, mammals, and even some
non-mammalian species. Precisely because they are part of our
evolutionary heritage, Ekman argued that these basic emotions
are universal across cultures -- everybody has them, whether
they're Germans or Japanese, Canadian or Zulu, and everybody
expresses them the same way on the face, and everybody
recognizes these facial expressions.
Ekman's list of basic
emotions varies a little from account to account, but these
six remain constant:
- Happiness
- Sadness
- Fear
- Anger
- Surprise
- Disgust
Of course, we can feel a lot more
different emotions than that. Ekman's theory proposes that
these other emotions arise as blends of basic emotions. Or,
perhaps, there are specifically human emotions, not shared
with other primates, that are generated by processes other
than the universal, innate, hard-wired processes that
automatically generate the basic emotions.
What About Positive Emotions?
One
thing to note in Ekman's list of basic emotions is that while
there are four negative emotions (sadness, fear, anger, and
disgust), each linked to avoidance behaviors; there is only
one positive emotion (happiness). Recently, Michelle
Shiota, working with UCB's Prof. Dacher Keltner and others,
has proposed a list of discrete positive emotions (Am.
Psych., 2017). Shiota et al. differentiate among
at least nine positive emotions, which they depict as
"branches" of a "tree" whose "trunk" represents enthusiasm
-- or Ekman's basic emotion of happiness. Much as each
of Ekman's basic emotions is rooted in a distinct facial
expression, Shiota et al. argue that each positive emotion is
mediated by a specific neurotransmitter system which shapes
undifferentiated enthusiasm into a specific positive
emotion. But it's not just a matter of
neurotransmitters. In their view, each positive emotion
is a specialized response to particular resources or
opportunities.
For example, the basic positive emotion
of enthusiasm (happiness) is rooted in the
dopaminergic reward system of the brain, geared toward
acquiring many different kinds of resources, from food to
sexual pleasure. Shiota et al.'s list of discrete
positive emotions follows. Note that emotions which
share a common neurotransmitter system are further
differentiated by the context in which the emotion is
experienced.
Discrete Positive Emotion |
Associated
Neurotransmitter System |
Typical Resource/Opportunity |
Liking/pleasure | Opioid Peptides | Consummatory Behavior |
Attachment Love | Opioid Peptides (Love Is An
Addiction!) |
Coordinated Social Behavior |
Gratitude | ? |
Unexpected Benefits |
Amusement |
Cannabinoids | Opportunities for Humor and Play |
Awe | Oxytocin |
Vast Information-Rich Environment |
Contentment | Oxytocin |
Satiety |
Nurturant Love | Oxytocin |
Parenting |
Sexual Desire | Testosterone (Men and
Women!) |
Sexual Opportunity/Stimulation/Activity |
Pride | Serotonin |
High Social Status |
Pixar Studios drew
on Ekman's work in constructing the characters of their 2015
movie, Inside Out. In the film, Riley, an
11-year-old girl, moves with her family from Minnesota to San
Francisco. Most of the movie takes place inside Riley's
mind, and especially the interactions among five emotions --
Joy, Anger, Disgust, Fear, and Sadness. The depictions
of these emotions are, in turn, based on instantly and
universally recognizable facial expressions of emotion.
Link to a UCB Press release about the involvement of Prof. Dacher Keltner in the production of Inside Out.
Link to a New York Times article about the depiction of Riley's memories as "islands" in her mind.
Link
to a New York Times article by Keltner and
Ekman, concerning "The Science Behind Inside Out"
While it's possible to argue,
as Tomkins did, that feedback from the facial musculature (or,
alternatively, the perception of facial action) creates the
subjective experience of emotion, Robert Zajonc proposed a
rather different mechanism in his vascular theory of
emotional efference. According to Zajonc, the actions of
the facial musculature affect breathing patterns, and the flow
of air through the nasal cavity, and particularly through a
structure known as the cavernous sinus. Changes in
airflow result in changes in brain temperature, which in turn
alters neurotransmitter activity, which in turn affects
hedonic tone. Put simply:
- Increasing brain temperature increases positive mood.
- Decreasing brain temperature increases negative mood.
Howard Leventhal, another
student of Tomkins', has incorporated facial activity into his
perceptual-motor theory of emotion. According to
Leventhal, emotion involves three separate systems.
- The expressive-motor processing system generates subjective feelings of emotion, and also expressive reactions on the face and elsewhere.
- Schematic/perceptual memory encodes emotional episodes in memory. But it also records the procedures that permit the rapid evaluation of environmental events, and the automatic activation of facial expressions and other emotional behaviors.
- A conceptual/abstract memory contains "semantic" knowledge about emotion, as well as nonverbal "procedural" knowledge required for the recognition and enactment of emotional expressions.
Affective Neuroscience
An alternative psychobiological approach to emotion has its roots in neuroscience rather than in evolutionary theory. Just like cognitive neuroscience, affective neuroscience is grounded in the general neuroscientific Doctrine of Modularity -- the idea that different parts of the brain are involved in different mental functions. Whereas cognitive neuroscience tries to identify the brain structures and systems that mediate cognitive functions such as perception, memory, and language, affective neuroscience tries to identify the brain structures and systems that mediate affective, or emotional, functions such as experiencing, perceiving, and expression emotional feeling states. A further implication of the Doctrine of Modularity is that there are separate brain structures or systems regulating each of the basic emotions, but for a number of reasons until recently almost all affective neuroscience has focused on fear.
Walter
Cannon's critique of the James-Lange theory led him and others
(like Duffy) to think of emotion as entailing an
undifferentiated state of autonomic arousal. What generates
autonomic arousal? Why, the hypothalamus, of course. Thus,
Cannon and his student, Philip Bard, proposed a hypothalamic
theory of emotion. As its name implies, the theory
proposes that emotional state (remember, according to Cannon,
there's just one emotional state, associated with flight or
fight) is generated by the hypothalamus. Discharges from the
hypothalamus to the brainstem, and thus down the spinal cord
(and, for that matter, out onto the face) are responsible for
emotional behavior, while discharges from the hypothalamus to
the cerebral cortex are responsible for emotional experience.
The
Cannon-Bard theory was subsequently revised by James Papez, a
neuroanatomist who traced the connections between the
hypothalamus and other structures in the subcortical "limbic
lobe" of the brain. According to Papez, emotion involves not
just the hypothalamus but rather an entire circuit of
structures, including the hypothalamus, the anterior portion
of the thalamus, the anterior portion of the cingulate gyrus,
and the hippocampus. This set of structures is now known as Papez'
circuit. According to Papez' theory, emotion is not
generated solely by the hypothalamus, but rather by the
coordinated activity of a number of subcortical structures,
each performing its own special function:
- The thalamus, acting as s sensory relay station, processes information from the emotional stimulus.
- The hypothalamus generates the bodily response to the emotional stimulus -- much as in the Cannon-Bard theory.
- The cingulate cortex generates the subjective feeling state.
Note, the name "Papez" may look Spanish, but James Papez (1883-1958) was actually an American of Czech descent, trained at the University of Minnesota, and taught at Cornell. I have heard every imaginable pronunciation of his name, including Papeth. But I have it on good authority (confirmed by someone else named James Papez) that the proper pronunciation is Payps (long a, one syllable).
Paul MacLean extended the general idea of
Papez' circuit (he also gave Papez' circuit its name) to other
structures in what Paul Broca called le lobe limbique,
because they form a border (L. limbus) around the
brainstem. MacLean gave the name limbic system to this
entire set of structures, including the amygdala,
orbitofrontal cortex, and parts of the basal ganglia), and
proposed that what he now called limbic system
comprised the "old mammalian brain" is the neural basis
of emotion.
You'll remember MacLean's
concept of the triune brain from the lectures on the
Biological Bases of Mind and Behavior. He argued that
evolution had actually given humans a set of three brains,
built one on top of the other.
- At the bottom is the R-Complex, or "Reptilian Brain", consisting of the brain stem and the cerebellum, which regulates vital functions and simple motor behaviors.
- At the top is the neocortex, the "new brain".
- In the middle is the limbic system, or "Old Mammalian brain" consisting of the amygdala, hypothalamus, hippocampus, and other structures of the limbic lobe.
Most recently, Joseph LeDoux and his
colleagues have proposed that a particular brain system serves
as the neural basis of fear. LeDoux's theory looks a lot like
Papez's, frankly, except that it is a little more elaborated,
taking into account Lang's multiple-system view of emotion.
Most important, it is supported by a large number of
behavioral experiments involving animals, brain-damaged
patients, and brain-imaging studies of neurologically intact
normal subjects.
- An emotional event is first processed through the thalamus, performing its usual function as a sensory relay station.
- Signals from the thalamus project to the amygdala, which generates both the behavioral and physiological responses to the emotional stimulus.
- Signals from both the thalamus and the amygdala project to the cerebral cortex, which generates the subjective experience of emotion.
Thus, LeDoux's model
provides the physiological basis for various desynchronies in
emotional behavior:
- For example, if the connection between the thalamus and the amygdala is broken, the subject will experience fear subjectively, but will not show any of the behavioral or physiological signs of fear (because these are generated by the amygdala, which isn't receiving any signals from the thalamus.
- Or, to take another example, if the connection is severed between the thalamus and the cortex, the subject will show the behavioral and physiological signs of fear, but will not have any subjective experience of fear.
Note that if the thalamus is damaged, the subject wouldn't show any signs, or have any experience of fear. That might lead investigators to conclude that the thalamus is the neural basis of fear. But, in this instance, presumably the subject would show other behavioral deficits as well, not just those involving fear, because the thalamus would not be able to perform any of its normal sensory-relay functions. In fact, the subject would be comatose, completely unresponsive to events in the environment, whether fearful or not; and unconscious; but he would still be alive, with vegetative functions performed by an intact brainstem.
LeDoux has worked out the brain systems for fear in some detail, and his theory is widely accepted. But he's only worked out the details for fear. The implication of his theory is that a similar account can be given for other basic emotions, such as happiness, anger, and disgust.
In fact, affective neuroscientists,
working (as LeDoux has done) with animal models, brain-damaged
patients, and brain-imaging methods, have now begun to
identify the brain structures involved in other emotions, not
just fear.
- As suggested by LeDoux (and MacLean), the amygdala appears to play a special role in fear, and is critical for fear conditioning, and escape and avoidance learning.
- The orbitofrontal cortex, and the anterior cingulate gyrus, appears to mediate response to social violations, and may be the neural substrate of anger.
- The temporal pole of the right hemisphere seems to be associated with sadness and other negative emotions, and is implicated in withdrawal responses.
- The anterior portion of the insula (nicely located near the olfactory lobe), as well as the anterior cingulate gyrus, seems to be associated with feelings of disgust.
There also appears to be some hemispheric specialization for emotion. Based on electrophysiological and brain-imaging studies, Davidson (1992) has proposed that approach-related positive emotions are mediated by the frontal and anterior temporal regions of the left hemisphere, while withdrawal-related negative emotions are mediated by the same regions of the right hemisphere.
A somewhat humorous illustration of Davidson's theory comes from a study of tail-wagging behavior in dogs reported by by Vallortigara et al. (Current Biology, 2013). Dogs watching a video of another dog wagging its tail to the left showed physiological and behavioral signs of stress and anxiety -- but no such signs when watching a video of a dog wagging its tail to the left. Like left-handedness in people, left-tail-wagging in dogs is controlled by the right hemisphere. Therefore, the researchers suggest, tail-wagging to the left (sinistral tail-wagging: get it?) is generated by the right hemisphere, which is specialized for negative emotion; and other dogs can use the direction of tail-wagging as an emotional cue. At any rate, the findings suggest some degree of lateral specialization in dogs, as well as humans.
All of this is pretty preliminary, and
there are lots of details left to be worked out, but these
findings indicate how the Doctrine of Modularity might be
implemented in the emotional domain.
Physiological Correlates of Emotion
Emotions are mental states, but ever since James and Lange, and in response to Cannon's critique, psychologists and physiologists have searched for definitive physiological correlates of emotion. Many of these have been proposed -- perhaps most famously, Ekman's proposal that each of the half-dozen-or so basic emotions is associated with distinctive activity in the facial musculature. However, this view remains controversial. Lisa Feldman Barrett, a distinguished emotion researcher, has reviewed the evidence and found that there are no "unique, biological 'fingerprints'" of any emotional state (for a brief summary, see "What Emotions Are (And Aren't)", New York Times, 08/02/2015, from which the quote is drawn).
- Brain-imaging studies using fMRI and other techniques have revealed no distinctive pattern of brain activations associated with Ekman's basic emotions.
- Somewhat surprising, this includes the amygdala, a brain structure traditionally associated with fear.
- Even the case of SM, who lost her amygdala and also
her ability to experience fear, is ambiguous.
There are two identical twins, known in the literature
as BG and AM, who both have the same condition as SM,
which destroys the amygdala. But while BG has
difficulty experiencing fear, AM has no problem
experiencing fear or any other emotion.
- Nor do psychophysiological studies reveal any pattern of physiological activity, such as changes in heart rate, respiration, or skin conductance associated with specific emotional states.
- And, perhaps most surprising of all, the evidence for discrete patterns of activity in the facial musculature is also surprisingly weak.
Barrett concludes that happiness, fear, and
other emotional states vary widely in their biological
correlates. The different emotions are created by the
context in which these biological states occur -- a position
that is close to the cognitive-constructive view of Schachter
and Singer, Lazarus, and others.
The Embodied Mind
Recall,
from the first lecture, that Rene Descartes, the 17th-century
French philosopher, had argued for a strict separation of
body and mind. His
argument was so influential that it retarded the development
of psychology as a science.
And even after psychology became a full-fledged
science, most researchers assumed that mental life could be
understood without reference to the body – that they could
create an abstract “amodal architecture” of the mind. To the contrary,
the emotion theories of Tomkins, Ekman, Leventhal, and
others make a case for the embodiment of mind. By this we mean
that mental representations and processes – the very stuff
that psychology tries to understand – are grounded in their
physical context. This
physical context includes both the physical situation and,
especially, the physical body.
Embodiment affects cognitive processes such as
perception, memory, and language, too, but it is especially
prominent in the case of emotion. To a great extent,
our emotions are derived from our perceptions of our bodily
processes, and they are expressed in bodily form by facial
expressions, posture, and other gestures.
Jokes and Humor
And The Funniest Joke in the Whole World, Ever
One of the persisting puzzles in the psychology of emotion is why we find some things funny and others not (another puzzle is why we can't tickle ourselves). Put another way, why do we laugh? Psychologists will study anything, and wherever two or three psychologists study the same thing they form a society devoted to the subject, so there is also an International Society for Humor Studies and HUMOR: The International Journal of Humor Research.
Theories of humor have been proposed since
Aristotle, and most of them capture only a small part of the
action.
- Aristotle, Plato, and the British philosopher Thomas Hobbes favored what is known as superiority theory -- that we laugh when we appreciate our superiority to the object of the joke. This helps explain why, when someone takes a pratfall, our first impulse is often to laugh. As Mel Brooks once put it: "tragedy is if I cut my finger. comedy is if you walk into an open sewer and die".
- Sigmund Freud, for his part, proposed (in Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious, 1905) release theory, that jokes somehow make contact with unconscious sources of pleasure, by expressing taboo wishes having to do with sex and aggression. Along these lines, Dave Barry, the American humorist, has suggested that aggression, sexuality, and offensiveness are the "three building-blocks of humor".
- Henri Bergson, the French psychologist, proposed machine theory, that we laugh at the inflexibility of other people.
- Recently, even neuroscience has gotten into the act. Although the right hemisphere is sometimes characterized as "emotional", in contrast to the "rational" left hemisphere, humor probably requires the integrated activity of both hemispheres. It has been suggested, perhaps somewhat facetiously, that the left hemisphere sets up the joke, while the right hemisphere gets it. A 1981 paper by Wapner, Hamby, and Gardner, proposed that "While the left hemisphere might appreciate some of Grouch's puns, and the right hemisphere might be entertained by the antics of Harpo, only the two hemispheres united can appreciate a whole Marx Brothers routine".
- Perhaps the most popular theory of humor, incongruity theory, was initially proposed by Blaise Pascal, a 17th-century French philosopher. As he wrote, "Nothing produces laughter more than a surprising disproportion between that which one expects and that which one sees. Incongruity theory explains the humor we find in puns and plays on words. Punch lines are often incongruous with setups. Leo McCarey, the producer of many Hollywood comedies, including some starring Laurel and Hardy, proposed that comedy relies on a "rule of three": a running gag will set an example, repeat it, and then shatter it. The first two examples set up an expectation, which is violated by the gag itself. If the gag is repeated, it's not as funny as it was the first time, but it will become funny again if there are two straightforward setups.
- Of course, context matters too -- it helps if you know that a joke is a joke. W.F. Fry and Gregory Bateson, two anthropologists, have argued that jokes work only within a play frame established by a setup or metacue that a joke is coming.
Richard Wiseman of the University of Hertfordshire, in England, runs a "LaughLab" website (www.LaughLab.co.uk) that, among other things, searched for the world's funniest joke. Visitors to the website submitted jokes for consideration, and were also given the opportunity to rate a sample of jokes on a 5-point scale called a Giggleometer. This technique is not entirely foolproof. Dave Barry once asked readers of his syndicated newspaper column to send in jokes featuring the punchline, "There's a weasel chomping on my privates", and to give other weasel-chomping jokes high ratings. And, perhaps because LaughLab was a government project, Wiseman and his colleagues filtered out jokes with sexual, scatological, racist, violent, or other offensive content, and bowdlerized ethnic jokes (see below). Still, Wiseman and his colleagues obtained some findings that make sense -- for example, that the presence of a duck makes a joke funnier than any other animal.
For a long time, the world's funniest joke went something like this:
Sherlock Holmes and Dr. Watson were went camping and pitched their tent in a clearing. During the night, Holmes awakened Watson: "Watson! Look up! What do you see?" Watson replied, "Why, Holmes, I see the moon and the stars". "And what do you conclude from this, Watson?", Holmes said. "That the weather will be fair tomorrow", Watson replied. "No Watson, you idiot!" Holmes screamed. "Somebody stole our tent!"
In October 2002, however, Wiseman and his colleagues finally identified the absolutely funniest joke in the world, which goes like this (as reported in "What's So Funny", by Tad Friend, New Yorker, 11/11/02, from which some of this section is derived):
A couple of New Jersey hunters are out in the woods when one of them falls to the ground. He doesn't seem to be breathing, his eyes are rolled back in his head. The other guy whips out his cell phone and calls the emergency services. He gasps to the operator, "My friend is dead! What can I do?" The operator, in a calm soothing voice, says, "just take it easy. I can help. First, let's make sure he's dead." There is a moment of silence, then a shot is heard. The guy's voice comes back on the line. he says, "OK, now what?".
Mary Beard, a classicist, summarizes three broad classes of theories concerning of laughter (in Laughter in ancient Rome: On Joking, Tickling, and Cracking Up, 2014):
- Superiority theory holds that laughter is a form of mockery.
- Incongruity theory, laughter is a response to illogical or unexpected events.
- Relief theory views laughter as a release from pent-up emotion.
Beard points out that while primates are sometimes observed to laugh, in fact there are differences:
- Humans laugh in a single exhalation: hahaha!
- Primates' laughter is more panting, with each exhalatory
ha! followed by an inhalation.
Still, the whole thing is pretty much a mystery.
Further reading:
- For a classic study of humor, see Jokes and their Relation to the Unconscious by Sigmund Freud (1905) -- which is, thankfully, mostly free of psychoanalytic nonsense.
- For a more recent summary of the scientific research on
humor, see The Humor Code: A Global Search for What
Makes Things Funny (2014) by Peter McGraw and Joel
Warner
Cognitive Effects on Emotion
This course is agnostic with respect to the Kantian assertion that cognition and emotion, knowledge and feeling, are independent faculties of mind. While some cognitive and social psychologists, following the lead of Schachter and Singer, offered theories of emotion as a cognitive construction, other psychologists, largely influenced by the neuroscientific Doctrine of Modularity, argued that emotion was, at least in some respects, independent of cognition.
For organizational purposes, these lectures have assumed, with Kant, that emotion is at least to some extent independent of cognition -- that is, that at least some emotions are somehow basic, irreducible features of mental life. This might not actually be true (though I think it is) -- though behaving as if it is true provides ample justification for giving emotion (and motivation, for that matter) some treatment in the course separate from cognition.
But that doesn't mean that emotion and cognition are wholly independent of each other. Even if emotions are not cognitive constructions, it is clear that changing how we perceive, remember, and think about events changes our emotional reaction to them. And remembering one event (or one aspect of an event) as opposed to another will change our mood.
Mood-Induction Techniques
As an example of the effect of
cognition on emotion, consider the Velten Mood-Induction
Technique, commonly used in early studies of emotion.
The technique consists of two sets of 58 sentences, one
positive and one negative, each worded in the first
person. The idea is that by reading through these
self-referential statements, the subject will take on the
underlying positive or negative mood.
Here are the 58 "positive" statements
(the negative statements are real downers, and I don't want my
readers to be unhappy!):
1. Today is neither better nor worse than any other day
2. I do feel pretty good today, though
3. I feel light-hearted
4. This might turn out to have been one of my good days
5. If your attitude is good, then things are good and my attitude is good
6. I feel cheerful and lively
7. I've certainly got energy and self-confidence to share
8. On the whole, I have very little difficulty in thinking clearly
9. My friends & family are pretty proud of me most of the time
10. I’m in a good position to make a success of things
11. For the rest of the day, I bet things will go really well
12. I'm pleased that most people are so friendly to me
13. My judgments about most things are sound
14. The more I get into things the easier they become for me
15. I'm full of energy and ambition - I feel like I could go a long time without sleep
16. This is one of those days when I can get things done with practically no effort at all
17. My judgment is keen and precise today. Just let someone try to put something over me
18. When I want to, I can make friends extremely easily
19. If I set my mind to it, I can make things turn out fine
20. I feel enthusiastic and confident now
21. There should be opportunity for a lot of good times coming along
22. My favorite songs keep going through my mind
23. Some of my friends are so lively and optimistic
24. I feel talkative - I feel like talking to almost anybody
25. I'm full of energy, and am really getting to like the things I'm doing
26. I feel like bursting with laughter - I wish somebody would tell a joke and give me an excuse
27. I feel an exhilarating animation in all I do
28. My memory is in rare form today
29. I'm able to do things accurately and efficiently
30. I know good and well that I can achieve the goals I set
31. Now that it occurs to me, most of the things that have depressed me wouldn't have if I'd just had the right attitude
32. I have a sense of power and vigor
33. I feel so vivacious and efficient today - sitting on top of the world
34. It would really take something to stop me now
35. In the long run, it's obvious that things have gotten better and better during my life
36. I know in the future I won't over-emphasize so-called "problems"
37. I'm optimistic that I can get along very well with most of the people I meet
38. I'm too absorbed in things to have time for worry
39. I'm feeling amazingly good today
40. I am particularly inventive and resourceful in this mood
41. I feel superb! I think I can work to the best of my ability
42. Things look good Things look great!
43. I feel that many of my friendships will stick with me in the future
44. I feel highly perceptive and refreshed
45. I can find the good in almost everything
46. In a buoyant mood like this one, I can work fast and do it right the first time
47. I can concentrate hard on anything I do
48. My thinking is clear and rapid
49. Life is so much fun; it seems to offer so many sources of fulfillment
50. Things will be better and better today
51. I can make decisions rapidly and correctly; and I can defend them against criticisms easily
52. I feel industrious as heck - I want something to do!
53. Life is firmly in my control
54. I wish somebody would play some good loud music!
55. This is great -- I really do feel good. I am elated about things!
56. I'm really feeling sharp now
57. This is just one of those days when I'm ready to go!
58. Wow, I feel great!
Emotional Self-Regulation
It is also clear from the literature on emotional self-regulation that we can control our emotional responses to various events -- and that we do so largely through cognitive transformations of various kinds.
Richard Lazarus (1966), a clinical psychologist, focused on the role of cognitive processes in the self-regulation of emotion. Basically, he argued that we could change our emotional reaction to an event by changing the way we perceive or categorize that event. As with Schachter and Singer, then, emotion is viewed as an consequent of cognitive activity.
Although Lazarus proposed a general cognitive-appraisal theory of emotion, his own research focused on stress and coping in medical contexts. Here, he argued, problem-focused coping is not always possible: you've got a disease, the procedures involved in diagnosis and treatment may be unpleasant, and the outcome may not be good, and all of that is more or less out of the patient's hands. Accordingly, for medical patients, the best approach is emotion-focused coping processes, which attempt to regulate the patient's emotional response to illness and its treatment.
To give you an idea of what Lazarus had in mind, let me provide a personal anecdote. There came a time in my life when, as a consequence of a poorly done filling, my dentist told me I should have a root canal. Now, even with lots of anesthetics a root canal is a fairly unpleasant procedure. But as we discussed it, he made clear that, so far as dentists were concerned, root canals were the greatest thing since sliced bread, because, as he put it, "We can now save teeth!". Before the root canal, all dentists could do in such situations was to extract the diseased tooth, which creates other problems down the road. This information changed my view of root canals, and my emotional state both before and during the procedure, dramatically. And when, later, I had to have another root canal, it didn't faze me a bit. Changing the way I perceived the procedure changed my emotional reaction to it.
Emotional Effects on Cognition
And just as
cognition can have an effect on emotion, so emotion can have
an effect on cognition. That is, the way we are feeling can
influence what we perceive, and think, and remember.
Emotion and Memory
Most of early research on
emotion-cognition interactions focused on memory. Research has
identified a number of emotional influences on what, and how,
we remember the past. These influences come in two broad
categories:
- Effects of the subject's mood state at the time of encoding or retrieving a memory.
- Effects of the emotional valence of the material being encoded or retrieved.
Perhaps the most dramatic of effect of
emotion on memory is mood-dependent memory (MDM),
already discussed in the lectures on Memory as an example of
context-dependent memory and the Encoding Specificity
Principle. Memory is better when the mood of the subject at
the time of retrieval matches his or her mood at the time of
encoding. Put another way, memory is better when both encoding
and retrieval take place in the same emotional mood state,
compared to different mood states. In principle, MDM is
independent of the emotional valence of the items being
encoded and retrieved. In the classic case, MDM occurs for
affectively neutral items.
MDM is hard to get in the laboratory, but it has been clearly documented by Eich and Metcalfe (see the Lecture Supplement on 'Memory").
There
is also an affective valence effect,where memory is
better for material that has a positive emotional valence,
compared to neutral or negative items.
Boucher and Osgood (1969) labeled the emotional valence effect the Pollyanna Principle, after the title character in a series of classic children's books by Eleanor H. Porter. Pollyanna Whittier, an orphan, gets through girlhood by playing the "glad game", always looking on the sunny side of life, and always thinking the best of other people. Pollyanna optimism is challenged when, as a result of a traffic accident, she loses both her legs.Spoiler alert: But still, she resolves to be glad that she once had legs, and her positive outlook carries her through her time at a rehabilitation hospital, where she learns to walk again. Matlin and Stang (1978) presented a host of evidence that the Pollyanna Principle influences every aspect of cognition.
The emotional valence effect is not to be confused with the Freudian concept of repression. Freud viewed repression as something that happened to material related to primitive sexual and aggressive motives that conflict with social strictures. David Rapaport, an important post-Freudian psychoanalytic theorist, was always at pains to emphasize that repression did not occur for material that was "merely unpleasant". But that's precisely what the emotional valence effect is: a general tendency to forget items that are "merely unpleasant" and disagreeable.
Interestingly, there is also support for
an affective intensity effect, such that memory is
generally better for material that carries some affective
valence, whether positive or negative, compared to neutral
material.
The affective intensity effect is a special case of the Von Restorff Effect (von Restorff, 1933), which refers to the fact that memory tends to favor salient events -- the more an event stands out against its background, the better it will be remembered. And the idea is that affective valence increases salience.
Of course, if you think about
it, there's something of a contradiction between the affective
valence effect and the affective intensity effect. The
affective valence effect implies that negatively toned
material will be poorly remembered, compared to neutral
material, while the affective intensity effect implies that it
will be better remembered. The apparent contradiction can be
resolved by suggesting that there is actually a J-shaped
function relating affective valence and memory. The J-function
occurs, in this argument, because some affective intensity is
better than none, even if it's negative, and this boosts the
memorability of negative items; or, to put it another way, the
affective valence effect suppresses the memorability of
negative items somewhat, but they still get some advantage of
affective intensity.
There's actually a fair amount of evidence for this J-shaped function relating emotional valence and memory, but Banaji and Hardin (1994) pointed out a subtle problem. They argued that, on average, positive events are more arousing than negative events. That is to say, for most of us anyway, the good things that happen to us are really good, and the bad things that happen to us aren't so bad. Not to mention that most of us experience more good things than bad things. They further argued that when you control for differential intensity, the affective valence effect disappears. That is, negative events are no less memorable than positive events, provided that they're equivalent in intensity. So there's still an open question: Whether there is an affective valence effect independent of affect intensity.
In principle, anyway, the affective intensity effect is independent of affective valence -- that is, it occurs regardless of whether the items are positively or negatively toned. That raises the question of the effects of general physiological arousal on memory. That is, what is the effect of the subject's state of physiological arousal on memory, regardless of whether she feels bad or feels good?
In fact, research on arousal and task
performance yielded one of the earliest psychological "laws":
the Yerkes-Dodson Law. Announced in 1908, it's not as
old as Weber's Law or Fechner's Law, but still pretty old.
Yerkes and Dodson proposed that arousal was related to task
performance (any task) by an inverted U-shaped function.
That is, for any task there is some intermediate level of
arousal which optimizes performance. Think of this as like
Aristotle's "happy medium" (in the Eudemian Ethics) or
"Golden Mean" (in the Nicomachean Ethics) -- not to
mention the fairy tale of "Goldilocks and the Three Bears").
- At lower levels of arousal, performance is poor because no behavior is activated (in the extreme case, the subject is fatigued, drowsy, asleep or comatose).
- At higher levels of arousal, performance is poor because many different behaviors are activated, and these compete and interfere with each other. Or, perhaps, high levels of arousal increase the processing load imposed on the subject, effectively diminishing the amount of attentional resources that can be devoted to the task.
The Yerkes-Dodson Law can apply to both encoding (learning) and retrieval (remembering).
The Yerkes-Dodson Law has very wide applicability in psychology, but at least in the case of memory the effects of arousal may be qualified by the length of the retention interval. In 1963 and 1964, Kleinsmith and Kaplan reported experiments in which they recorded subjects' level of physiological arousal (looking at a psychophysiological measure called the electrodermal response) while they a list of nonsense syllables. Based on this measure, they identified, for each subject, some items that stimulated high levels of arousal, and others that did not. After either a short or long retention interval, the subjects were asked to recall the items they had studied. Kleinsmith and Kaplan discovered that, over short retention intervals, items associated with relatively high levels of arousal were poorly remembered. But over long retention intervals, these same items were remembered relatively well. This interaction between arousal level and retention interval is now known as the Kleinsmith-Kaplan Effect.
The fact that an item could be poorly remembered over short retention intervals, but well remembered over longer retention intervals, indicates that the items associated with high levels of arousal are not merely poorly encoded. If they were poorly encoded, they'd simply be forgotten. Explaining the Kleinsmith-Kaplan effect isn't easy, but one prominent hypothesis is that high arousal levels effectively protect the newly encoded memory trace during the consolidation period. This "protective barrier" (as it were) impairs retrieval over short retention intervals, but after the memory has solidified the barrier dissipates, leaving the new memory more accessible over longer retention intervals.
The Yerkes-Dodson Law, and the Kleinsmith and Kaplan effect, have to do strictly with arousal levels, and do not depend on the subject's specific emotional state. But, in addition to mood-dependent memory, there are several effects of specific emotional states --differentiated arousal -- on memory.
One of these, identified by Ellis and
Ashbrook (1988, 1989), is known as the resource allocation
effect. Recall the distinction, discussed in the
lectures on Memory, between automatic and controlled
processes. Controlled processes consume attentional resources,
while automatic processes do not. Reviewing research on the
effects of depression on memory, Ellis and Ashbrook concluded
that depression impaired performance on effortful memory tasks
such as recall and recognition (especially free recall), but
had no effect on automatic tasks, such as priming effects.
More generally, depression impairs explicit memory, but not
implicit memory.
Why should this be so? There are, in fact, a number of mechanisms by which the resource-allocation effect could occur.
- Depression might simply diminish the subject's motivation to perform the task, so that he does not allocation enough attentional resources to it.
- Depression itself might directly diminish the attentional resources available to support task performance.
- Depressed subjects might be distracted by depressing thoughts, which effectively subtracts from the attentional resources available.
The resource allocation effects of depression on memory raise the interesting question of what the effects of mania -- a state of pathological elation -- might have on memory. You read this here first.
Another set of effects is known as mood-congruent
memory (MCM), which has to do with the match between the
emotional valence of the material (positive or negative) and
the subject's mood (positive or negative). And, at least there
are two kinds of MCM:
- In mood-congruent encoding, the subject's mood is varied at the time of encoding positive and negative material, and then retrieval is attempted in a neutral mood.
- In mood-congruent retrieval, the subject encodes positive and negative material in a neutral mood, and then attempts retrieval in a neutral mood.
MCM might be a special case of mood-dependent memory, based on the assumption that positive events induce positive moods, and negative events induce negative moods. For this reason, while studies of MCM must employ affectively valenced material (because the material has to be congruent or incongruent with the subject's mood state), the best studies of MDM use affectively neutral material.
MDM is interesting on clinical grounds, because it may reinforce low mood in depressed individuals. If being depressed makes it more likely that you'll encode unhappy events, then there will be more negative events available in memory. And if being depressed makes it more likely that you'll retrieve unhappy events from a memory store that is already biased toward unhappiness, you'll get even more depressed than you already are! And if being depressed makes it less likely that you'll remember the happy times, then it will be more difficult to snap yourself out of it. Throw MDM on top of MCM, and depressed individual will be more likely to remember events encoded during previous episodes of depression, precipitating a vicious spiral downward in mood. So, even if it turns out that clinical depression is purely biological in origin, the effects of mood on memory are likely to make things even worse.
There also have been claims for mood-incongruent memory, such that memory is best when happy subjects attempt to encode or retrieve negative material, or sad subjects attempt to encode or retrieve positive material. The claim is not unreasonable. If you think of mood operating analogously to a cognitive schema, providing a kind of emotional (rather than cognitive) framework for perception and memory, we would expect to find both "schema"-congruent and "schema"-incongruent information remembered better than "schema"-irrelevant material. However, occasional reports of mood-incongruency have not been independently confirmed, so -- unlike the other effects described here -- the effect cannot (yet) be considered reliable.
All these effects can be represented in the following table:
A General Experimental Framework
for Studying Emotional Effects on Memory
|
||||||
Encoding Mood |
Retrieval Mood |
|||||
Happy
|
Neutral
|
Sad
|
||||
Happy |
1 |
+ |
10 |
+ |
19 |
+ |
2 |
0 |
11 |
0 |
20 |
0 |
|
3 |
- |
12 |
- |
21 |
- |
|
Neutral |
4 |
+ |
13 |
+ |
22 |
+ |
5 |
0 |
14 |
0 |
23 |
0 |
|
6 |
- |
15 |
- |
24 |
- |
|
Sad |
7 |
+ |
16 |
+ |
25 |
+ |
8 |
0 |
17 |
0 |
26 |
0 |
|
9 |
- |
18 |
- |
27 |
- |
|
+ = Positive Material; 0 = Neutral Material; - = Negative Material |
Here are predictions for various combinations of cells:
Emotional Valence Effect: |
Cell 13 > Cell 14 > Cell 15 |
Emotional Intensity Effect: |
Cells 13 and 15 > Cell 14 |
Resource Allocation Effect on Encoding:Resource Allocation Effect on Retrieval: |
Cells 11 and 17 > Cell 14Cells 05 and 23 > Cell 14 |
Mood-Dependence Effects |
Cells 0 and 26 > Cell 14 > Cells 08, 20 |
Mood-Congruent EncodingMood-Congruent Retrieval |
Cells 10, 18 > Cells 13, 15 > Cells 12, 16Cells 04, 24 > Cells 13, 15 > Cells 06, 22 |
Emotion and Judgment
There are also studies of the effects of mood on judgment, many of which have been performed by Joseph Forgas and his colleagues, and Jennifer Lerner and her colleagues. Forgas finds that, in general, people are more risk-averse when in a negative mood, but Lerner has found more subtle effects when she takes into account different kinds of negative emotional states, such as sadness or anger.
Emotion and Perception
And finally, Paul Niedenthal and her colleagues, among others, have followed up on Bruner's original "New Look" by examining the effects of perception on emotion -- represented, for example, in her book, edited with Shinobu Kitayama, The Heart's Eye: Emotional Influences in Perception and Attention (1994).
Prospects for a Psychology of Emotion
There was a time when psychologists were strongly interested in emotion. Experiments on fear conditioning and avoidance learning played an important role in advancing our understanding of both classical and instrumental conditioning. Mowrer's two-factor theory of avoidance learning is all about the emotion of fear. And so is Cannon's idea that the autonomic nervous system serves as the biological basis of the "flight or fight" response, where something like fear seems to be the instigator for these self-protective behaviors.
Still, scientific Interest in emotion was undermined by the radical behaviorism of John B. Watson and B.F. Skinner, who argued that psychology should confine itself to tracing the functional associations between environmental stimuli and organismal responses, without speculating about internal emotional states (or cognitive or motivational states either, for that matter). Skinner used positive reinforcement in almost all of his studies, so he never had to find a behavioristic substitute for words like "fear". But it never occurred to him to define positive (or negative) reinforcement in terms of the pleasure (or unpleasure) that it gave the animal. Reinforcement was simply an environmental event that increased the probability of whatever behavior preceded it.
The cognitive revolution allowed psychologists to talk about emotion and other internal, mental states again -- even in nonhuman animals. But cognition dominated psychological talk. To the extent that psychologists talked about emotions at all, they tended to think of them, as in the Schachter-Singer experiment, as derived from cognition. We don't feel things, we just think we do. As a result, cognitive psychology became a major enterprise in the field -- really, the dominant subfield of psychology, with a whole host of undergraduate courses, textbooks, and graduate training groups. By comparison, the psychology of emotion garnered relatively little academic attention.
But the cognitive revolution in
psychology eventually spurred what I think of as an
affective counterrevolution. A purely cognitive
explanation of behavior seemed too cold and dry to some social
psychologists, who began to argue for "hot" cognition, in
which emotions (and motives) played a more central role. Even
before the cognitive revolution, Jerome Bruner and others
argued for a "New Look" in perception, which began with the
assumption that feelings and needs affected even "elementary"
cognitive processes like perception. In response to
cognitive-appraisal theorists like Lazarus, Zajonc and others
began to argue that affect, or at least some emotional states,
arose independently of cognition -- as in Zajonc's 1980 paper
entitled "Feeling and Thinking: Preferences Need No
Inferences" (a lively debate ensued between Zajonc and Lazarus
in the pages of the American Psychologist). Much
post-Zajonc research on emotion has had a decidedly
non-cognitive slant to it, heavily influenced by evolutionary
psychology on the one hand, and the neuroscientific Doctrine
of Modularity on the other. In any event, the emotion is back
in psychology again. If there are relatively few graduate
groups explicitly formed around the topic (though there are
some), undergraduate courses and textbooks have begun to
appear on the scene, and the topic is more popular than ever
before.
This page last modified
02/10/2019.