John F.
Kihlstrom
University
of California, Berkeley
As their last
writing assignment, I sometimes asked students in my
Introductory Psychology course to discuss something that they
learned in the course that surprised them, or challenged their
understanding of mind and behavior in some way, or was
particularly interesting or useful to them. In 2017, 50 years
after I took “Intro” myself as a college sophomore (at Colgate
University in Fall 1967, taught by William E. Edmonston, Jr.,
who also introduced me to hypnosis research), I taught intro for
the last time (after almost 40 years with the course). So I took the
opportunity to set down my own reflections on how psychology, as
represented by the introductory course, has changed in half a
century.
The textbook for
my intro psych course
was by Clifford Morgan and Robert King, two physiological
psychologists, and it was one of the best available at the time (Morgan & King, 1966, 3rd
edition, henceforth known as M&K or 3e) At the time I wrote my
own essay, in 2017, I did not have access to M&K. Nor was I able to
access the course syllabus or my class notes, which were lost
(along with the textbook) to a flooded basement while I was
teaching at Harvard. So
I had to reconstruct things from memory. Since then, I’ve
obtained a copy of the
text, and found that my memory was inaccurate in some
respects – a good illustration of the “Reconstruction Principle”
of memory (Kihlstrom, 1996). But it wasn’t bad –
also an illustration of the Reconstruction Principle. This version of my
essay has been revised to reflect my re-acquaintance with
M&K. (Disclaimer:
This essay is highly impressionistic, and the references in it
are high selective, if not highly arbitrary as well.)
Looking at the
book from the vantage point of 50 years later, pretty much
everything about psychology has changed – beginning with Morgan
and King’s specializations.
What was then called “physiological” psychology is now
usually called some form of neuroscience – systems, behavioral,
cognitive, affective, etc.
But there have been more than just changes in
nomenclature. Lots
more. What follows
is not intended to be a comprehensive update of M&K, much
less a synoptic view of the last 50 years of psychology. It’s more of an
impressionistic look backward over the last half-century, with
an emphasis on the trends, researchers, and theorists who have
interested me the most.
Defining Psychology
In their introduction, M&K
defined psychology as “the science of human and animal behavior”
(p.4) – a definition commensurate with the behaviorism of John
B. Watson and B.F. Skinner which dominated psychology at the
time. William
James, of course had defined psychology as the science of mental
life, but Watson and Skinner changed all that. As R.S. Woodworth put
it in his 1918 book, written in the aftermath of Watson’s
behaviorist manifesto, "First psychology lost its soul, then it
lost its mind, then it lost consciousness; it still has
behavior, of a kind" (p. 2).
M&K were not die-hard Skinnerian behaviorists,
though. Rather,
they were what you might call “methodological behaviorists”. As they wrote (p.4):
Behavior, rather than mind or thoughts or
feelings, is the subject of psychology because it alone can be
observed, recorded, and studied…..
We do, indeed, infer that mental processes take place and
that people think and feel, but for systematic knowledge of
psychological events we are limited to the observation of
behavior.
So, for M&K, behavior offers a
window on the mind. Reading
their definition, I was reminded that Noam Chomsky, somewhere,
quipped that psychology is no more the science of behavior than
physics is the science of meter-reading (J. S. Searle, 1972). But beginning in 1956
(George Miller gives the exact date as September 11; see) (Miller, 2003), and especially
after 1967, following publication of Ulric Neisser’s (Neisser, 1967) Cognitive Psychology,
the cognitive revolution legitimized talk about mental states
and processes once again, and psychologists returned to defining
their field as the science of the mind – or, perhaps more
broadly, as the science of mind and behavior – with “mind” coming first, and with
behavior of individuals construed as caused by their mental
states.[1]
Methods
and Statistics
M&K also lacked a free-standing
chapter on methods and
statistics, usually the second chapter encountered in
standard introductory texts.
However, in their introductory chapter they did
distinguish among “experimental” methods, investigating the
effect of independent variables manipulated by the experimenter
on dependent variables; “systematic observation” (we would now
call them “correlational” methods) of variables that cannot be
controlled by an experimenter; and the “clinical method”
involving case studies intended to understand the behavior of a
single individual. They
briefly discussed the problem of experimenter bias (e.g.,) (Rosenthal, 1963), but there
was no mention of demand characteristics and other problems of
ecological validity (Orne, 1962)
that would instigate one of social psychology’s earliest crises. Nor, aside from a
brief discussion of graphing to represent the relationships
between IVs and DVs, was there any substantive presentation in
of statistical methods, not even the t test and correlation
coefficient, probability levels, Type I and Type II errors, and
the like – at least until the chapter on “Individual
Differences”, where a couple of formulas are introduced.
Today, we still recognize the basic
distinction between what Cronbach (Cronbach, 1957) called “the
two disciplines of scientific psychology”, experimental and
correlational. But
our methods have gone far beyond the t test, ANOVA, and the
correlation coefficient. Today
even at the introductory level, there is likely to be a
discussion of “The New Statistics” (Cumming, 2014), problems with
null hypothesis significance tests, power analyses, and the
like. There is also
likely to be a discussion of the replication crisis. Sadly, the discussion
of research ethics, which used to revolve around preventing harm
to subjects, now must include injunctions not to fabricate data.
Biological
Psychology
To begin with, I should also say
something about the organization of M&K, which was a little
unorthodox. Over
the years, a canonical syllabus has developed for the
introductory course, which begins, after an introductory chapter
and a chapter on methods and statistics, with a chapter or two
on the nervous system and other biological bases of mind and
behavior. Personality
and social psychology come near the end – chiefly because, as
one wag (Daryl Bem?) once put it, we don’t want the intro
students who serve in our experiments in order to meet their
“Research Participation Requirement” to read about the Milgram (Milgram, 1963) experiment and
find out about deception. And
“abnormal” psychology always comes last, because – well, because
it’s abnormal.
In large part, an early discussion of
biology acknowledges that the brain is the physical basis of
mind, and helps establish psychology as a “real” science, like
biology itself, but there’s no reason to do it this way. For example, William
James began his Principles of Psychology (1890) with a chapter
on habit, before turning to the brain. I always liked the
suggestion of Jeff Greenberg, my former colleague at Arizona,
that the brain should come last: after we discuss how the mind
works, then we talk about how the brain does it. Very few authors have
tried this, though M&K did: their first substantive chapter
was on development, and they saved their chapters on the
“Nervous System and Internal Environment” and the “Physiological
Basis of Behavior” for the very last.
Anyway, M&K’s chapters on the biological bases of
behavior start out looking pretty much like a present-day
text, with a discussion of neurons, nerves, the autonomic and
central nervous system, and the like. But when it comes to
the cerebral cortex, everything is different. M&K knew about the
visual, auditory, somatosensory, and motor areas of the brain,
but most of the rest of cerebral cortex was characterized as
“association cortex” – as if the major portion the brain was an
undifferentiated information-processing machine. They understood that
Broca’s and Wernicke’s “speech” areas resided in the left
hemisphere, but took no account of the emerging
neuropsychological literature on hemispheric specialization (M.S. Gazzaniga, Bogen, & Sperry,
1962; Hecaen, 1962).
There was no mention of Patient H.M., and what he and
other amnesic patients could tell us about the role of the
hippocampus in conscious recollection (Scoville & Milner, 1957;
Warrington & Weiskrantz, 1968). But now, operating
under the neuroscientific Doctrine of Modularity, and combining
traditional neuropsychological analyses of brain-damaged
patients with advanced brain-imaging technologies like fMRI, we
know a great deal more about the functional specialization of
various parts of the brain, and about the organization of
various specialized brain modules into larger “circuits” and
“networks”. Current
“brain maps” outline literally dozens of areas which, alone and
in combination perform such specific functions as motion
perception, calculation, face recognition, shifting of
attention, memory consolidation, the classification of things
into living and nonliving, the labeling of emotional
expressions, and moral judgment (M.S.
Gazzaniga, Ivry, & Mangun, 2014). We are now even at the
point where we can see how specific thoughts and images are
represented in overall patterns of brain activity (Kay, Naselaris, Prenger, &
Gallant, 2008).
Moving beyond the nervous system, M&K had little to
say about behavior genetics except with respect to IQ. Now we have twin,
adoption, and other methods which allow us to measure not just
the genetic contributions to intelligence and other
characteristics, but the environmental contributions as well –
and, in particular, the important role played by the nonshared
environment in the development of many aspects of personality
and social interaction (Turkheimer,
Pettersson, & Horn, 2014; Turkheimer & Waldron, 2000).
M&K also had little to say about
hormones, aside from the role they play in emotion and in the
development of secondary sex characteristics. Today,
psychoneuroendocrinology is a vigorous field – e.g., research on the role of the
hypothalamic-pituitary-adrenal (HPA) axis in stress, the
hypothalamic-pituitary-gonadal (HPG) axis in dominance and
aggression, pheromones in sexual attraction, and oxytocin in
social bonding (Nemeroff &
Loosen, 1987). And
another new field, psychoneuroimmunology, underscores the role
that psychological factors can play in cancer and other medical
conditions (Segerstrom, 2012).
Evolution did not appear in the index
to M&K, nor was there any mention of the work of Karl von
Frisch, Konrad Lorenz, and Niko Tinbergen, who were to win the
Nobel Prize in 1973. While
recognizing that some behaviors, like nest-building in the
pregnant rat, were genetically determined, M&K generally
echoed the behaviorist critique of the concept of instinct. Today, however,
evolutionary psychology is a thriving enterprise in both
cognitive and social psychology, and providing a framework for
understanding emotion (Buss,
2009; Confer et al., 2010; Lewis, Al-Shawaf, Conroy-Beam,
Asao, & Buss, 2017).
While debate continues over specific claims (e.g.,) (C. R. Harris, 2003; Jones et al.,
2018) it now uncontroversial to assert that natural
selection and other evolutionary processes shape mind and
behavior as well as body morphology.
Learning
M&K had two chapters on learning, one for
classical and instrumental conditioning in animals, and another
for human learning. The latter material is now usually taught
under the rubric of “Memory”, and is discussed below. The conditioning
chapter focused mostly on descriptions of the various phenomena
of classical and instrumental conditioning, such as acquisition,
extinction, generalization, discrimination, and schedules of
reinforcement. Their
theoretical explanations of what was going on in conditioning
were a little thin, but generally focused on the contiguous
pairing of stimulus and response.
Although they discussed Tolman’s famous work on latent
learning, they focused on the role of reinforcement in
strengthening stimulus-response associations. Bandura’s (Bandura, 1962) work on
imitation and other forms of social learning, was not discussed
at all. Appreciation
of statistical (probabilistic) learning (Aslin & Newport, 2012),
another form of observational learning which does not depend on
reinforcement, was far in the future.
But soon, our whole understanding of
even simple forms of learning changed. Learning theory became
more biological with the discovery of preparedness and other
biological constraints on learning (Garcia, Ervin, & Koelling, 1966;
Rozin & Kalat, 1971; Seligman, 1970). And it became more
cognitive, with the experiments of Robert Rescorla (1967) and
Leon Kamin (1969), and the studies of learned helplessness by
Martin Seligman and his colleagues (1971). Learning theory became
more cognitive, with organisms acquiring expectations concerning
the outcomes of events (predictability) and behaviors
(controllability) rather than stimulus-response (Seligman, Maier, & Solomon,
1971).
Cognition
The cognitive revolution in psychology
was consolidated with the publication of Neisser’s (Neisser, 1967) Cognitive Psychology,
just a year after the publication of M&K’s third edition. But true to its
origins in British empiricism, scientific psychology had always
emphasized knowledge and its acquisition through experience, and
M&K were no exception.
They had two chapters on sensation, one each on
perception and memory, and another combining thinking and
language. But as
with learning theory, psychology was soon to take a more
expressly cognitive view of these topics, one that was more
focused on internal representation and processing.
The chapters on sensation (one on
vision, the other on hearing and the other modalities) were
organized mostly around sensory physiology, absolute and
differential thresholds, and classical psychophysics (e.g.,
Weber’s and Fechner’s laws).
Most of this material has stood the test of time, but
still there have been shifts and advances in our understanding. M&K gave equal
billing to the Young-Helmholtz trichromatic theory of color
vision and Hering’s opponent-process theory; now we’ve accepted
the latter as the better account (Hurvich
& Jameson, 1957).
The four traditional basic taste qualities discussed by
M&K have been supplemented by a fifth, umami (Yamaguchi, 1998); the “tongue
map” they described, in which receptors sensitive to each
quality are concentrated in separate areas of the tongue, is
wrong (Collings, 1974). We know that
pheromones, a special category of olfactory stimuli, affect
social (particularly sexual) behavior in humans as well as
nonhuman animals (McClintock,
2000). We
also know that “subliminal” perception, much debated, is a
genuine phenomenon – though we also know that claims for the
power of subliminal influence are exaggerated (Greenwald, Draine, & Abrams,
1996).
Most important, however, David Green
and John Swets (Green &
Swets, 1966) introduced signal-detection theory to the
study of sensation. Classical
psychophysics had viewed signal-detection as a simple matter of
stimulus intensity: if a stimulus were strong enough to cross
the modality’s “threshold” for sensation, it would be detected;
if not, not. In
this portrayal, the subjects are fairly passive – although they
can guess, or lose interest, and thus contaminate the
determination of thresholds.
But Green and Swets (Green
& Swets, 1966) portrayed the observer as an active
decision-maker and developed techniques that, by varying the
proportion of trials on which the stimulus was actually
presented (against a background of noise, to make detection more
of a challenge), and the rewards and penalties for hits and
misses, revealed the role that expectations and motives played
in even the most elementary psychological function: detecting
the presence of a stimulus in the environment. In so doing, they
blurred the conventional distinction between “lower” mental
processes of sensation and perception, and “higher” mental
processes of judgment and decision-making.
M&K’s chapter on perception was also
organized along traditional lines, with a focus on vision: cues
for the perception of motion and depth, and demonstrations of
familiar phenomena such as reversible figures, perceptual
constancies, and illusions.
They acknowledged Hubel and Wiesel’s (Hubel & Wiesel, 1959)
Nobel-winning research on feature-detection, but there was
nothing on pattern recognition in reading or speech perception. In 1966, too late to
make an appearance in M&K’s text, J.J. Gibson (Gibson, 1966) introduced his
“ecological” view of perception, point, stimulating a vigorous
debate with proponents of a more cognitive view of perception
promoted by people such as Richard Gregory (Gregory, 1970), Irvin Rock (Rock, 1975), Julian Hochberg
(Hochberg, 1978), and
others on the role of “bottom-up” versus “top-down” processes. Although there has
been resistance from some in the Gibsonian camp, altogether the
study of perception has gotten more cognitive – and again, with
brain imaging, we have a much better understanding of the neural
underpinnings of perception.
But there have been other
developments. Research
on “embodied” perception, for example, has revealed how feedback
from the sensory musculature influences visual perception (Proffitt, 2006, 2013). For example, wearing a
heavy backpack makes hills look steeper than they really are,
and grasping a baton makes objects which are within reach look
closer than they are (so long as they are within reach to begin
with). This
perspective has now spilled over into other domains of cognition
(Barlsalou, 2008), as
well as the study of emotion – which can be defined as the
perception of one’s own bodily responses to stimulus events (Niedenthal, Barsalou, Winkielman,
KrauthGruber, & Ric, 2005).
Although most research continues to
focus on vision (Palmer, 1999),
there has been more attention given to perception in other
modalities, especially audition.
The new interest in language, stimulated in large part by
Chomsky’s contribution to the cognitive revolution, gave rise to
research on speech perception (Liberman,
Cooper, Shankweiler, & Studdert-Kennedy, 1967) –
where the debate between “Gibsonians” and constructivists played
out on another field. And
psychologists began to study music, often in collaboration with
musicologists (Krumhansl, 1991,
2000, 2002). In
the domain of the chemical senses, a new basic taste, umami, has been added
to the traditional list of sweet, sour, salty, and bitter (and
the conventional “taste map” of the tongue has been largely
discredited. Research
has also shown how taste, smell, and even touch (what is known
as “crunch” or “mouth-feel” combine to affect the flavor of the
foods we eat. Perception
– it’s not just for vision scientists anymore.
M&K discussed memory in their
chapter on human learning, which focused on verbal learning in
the Ebbinghaus tradition. As
with animal learning, human learning also got the
stimulus-response treatment, with an emphasis on the
strengthening of links between paired associates by repetition,
and transfer of learning based on similarity of paired-associate
stimuli and responses. Modern
students of memory aren’t even taught this older literature as
historical background (more’s the pity). In another nod toward
stimulus-response behaviorism, they included a long discussion
of programmed learning and the teaching machines promoted by
B.F. Skinner. M&K
did discuss the distinction between short- and long-term memory,
which was one of the milestones of the cognitive revolution in
psychology (Atkinson &
Shiffrin, 1968), but our understanding of how memory
works is completely different from theirs. We now know a lot more
about the distinction between declarative (factual) and
procedural (skill) knowledge (Winograd,
1975), and between episodic and semantic forms of
declarative knowledge (Tulving,
1972), and about the mechanisms of encoding, storage,
and retrieval (Kihlstrom, 1996);
we know that remembering is less like taking a book off the
library shelf and reading it, and more like writing a book from
fragmentary notes (Roediger,
2000). And
we know a lot more about the neural bases of memory in the
hippocampus and other areas of the brain (Squire, Shimamura, & Amaral,
1989). Research
on the amnesic Patient H.M. began in the late 1950s (Scoville & Milner, 1957),
and instigated the revolution in cognitive neuroscience that I
alluded to above, but he got no mention in M&K’s book, and
the hippocampus – that structure in the medial temporal lobe
which, to make a long story short, is central to long-term
memory – barely got a mention (and then only in passing, as part
of the limbic system of subcortical structures involved with
emotion).
M&K’s chapter on thinking and language
was dominated by research on problem-solving, including
“vicarious trial-and-error” behavior (in which maze-running rats
look back and forth at a choice point before moving left or
right), functional fixedness, and Wallas’s analysis of creative
thinking into five “stages” of preparation, incubation,
illumination, evaluation, and revision.[2] Categorization, to the
extent that it was discussed at all, was viewed from the
perspective of the classical view of categories as proper sets. Their focus was on
Hull’s (Hull, 1920)
pioneering research on concept learning through generalization
and discrimination. About
a decade after publication of 3e, Eleanor Rosch (Rosch, 1975) overthrew 2500
years of authoritative wisdom about concepts and categories
(literally, since Aristotle!) and substitute the “fuzzy-set”
view of concepts represented by prototypes, exemplars, and
theories.
M&K did not discuss reasoning,
judgment, and decision-making in any detail. They had a section on
logical reasoning that owed more to Aristotle than to any
experimental research – though they did cover Newell and Simon’s
General Problem Solver (Newell,
Shaw, & Simon, 1958), a computer simulation of
human reasoning and problem-solving whose introduction was one
of the milestones of the Cognitive Revolution in psychology. At the time, most
discussions of reasoning, judgment, and decision-making revolved
around the Doctrine of Rational Choice, according to which
decision-makers sought to maximize the value of choices by
applying the principles of logic and probability – with perhaps,
as in M&K, a nod to the emotional, motivational, and
personal factors that led people to engage in illogical
thinking. Rational
choice had already been challenged by Herbert Simon (Simon, 1956), who proposed satisficing as a
substitute for maximizing, in work on organizational behavior
that was to win him the Nobel Prize in 1976. Later, Daniel Kahneman
and Amos Tversky (Tversky &
Kahneman, 1974) mounted their “heuristics and biases”
challenge to the Doctrine of Normative Rationality – work which
was to win Kahneman the 2002 Nobel Prize (by the time the award
was made, Tversky had died, making him ineligible). Along the way, Simon,
Kahneman and Tversky, and others revolutionized economics,
leading to the establishment of a new field, behavioral
economics, and a whole new approach to public policy, an
alternative to both libertarianism and government coercion,
according to which individuals are “nudged” into making
decisions that are in their best interests (Benartzi et al., 2017). Cognitive psychology
began with a focus on perception and attention, and then shifted
to memory. Now the
study of judgment and decision-making – how to make rational
choices under conditions of uncertainty (Christian & Griffiths, 2016;
Hastie & Dawes, 2010) is a major field in both
psychology departments and schools of business.
Actually, M&K had little to say
about language. In their chapter on
“Human Learning”, they had discussed the meaning of words in
terms of Osgood’s tridimensional theory of meaning, according to
which the meaning of any word can be represented in terms of its
location in a space defined by three dimensions: good vs. bad,
active vs. passive, and hard vs. strong.[3] M&K also discussed
language in their chapter on “Maturation and Development”, with
a focus on how children learned words by associating sounds with
objects. There was
no mention of Noam Chomsky, whose arguments against Skinner’s
analysis of “verbal behavior”, and for an innate “Universal
Grammar” (UG) underlying all natural languages, were another
hallmark of the cognitive revolution in psychology (Chomsky, 1957, 1959). Later, some
theorists argued against Chomsky’s idea that language learning
involved a specialized “Language Acquisition Device” (LAD), the
name he gave to a hypothetical module in the brain that was
dedicated to this task, and proposed instead that language
acquisition was simply a product of a more general capacity for
statistical or probability learning. This is an idea that
you could view as an updated version of the argument by Skinner
that Chomsky so vigorously and persuasively opposed – and you
wouldn’t be far wrong. The
debate goes on, but the general view is that while vocabulary
might be acquired through something like associative learning
(essentially the view presented in M&K), the acquisition of
grammatical rules was something else entirely, and really did
require something like a LAD built on an innate UG (S. M. Pinker, 1994).
Chomsky shifted the focus of
linguistics, which he defined as a branch of psychology, from
the study of semantics (words) to the study of syntax (grammar);
from the differences between languages to the similarities among
them; and from language as a tool for communication to language
as a tool for thought – a window on the mind (S. Pinker, 2007). His ideas had a
powerful impact on psychology, and not just in the study of
language. Chomsky
also became famous as a vehement opponent of the Vietnam War and
other aspects of American foreign and domestic policy. These two aspects of
his career were linked: in Chomsky’s view, the application of a
finite set of grammatical rules to a finite vocabulary enables
us to generate, and understand, an infinite number of meaningful
propositions – allows us to speak, and think, things that have
never been spoken or thought before. So far as we know, no
other animal has this creative linguistic capacity. From this point of
view, language is both the critical feature of human nature and
the cognitive substrate of human freedom (Chomsky, 1972).
Motivation and Emotion
Scientific psychology emerged from
British empiricism, which was primarily concerned with the
acquisition of knowledge through experience (and reflection on
experience). So it
is natural that the 19th century psychologists
emphasized problems of sensation and perception. Following the cognitive revolution
of 1956, consolidated by Neisser’s (Neisser, 1967) textbook,
scientific psychology focused on problems of memory, reasoning,
judgment, decision-making, and language, and the cognitive
viewpoint quickly spread to social and clinical psychology as
well. At the same
time, psychologists understood that there was more to mental
life than cognition. While
the label “cognitive” sometimes is employed to stand for all
sorts of internal mental states and processes (the sort of
things that the behaviorists abjured), cognition is really
about the acquisition, representation, transformation, and
utilization of knowledge,
and doesn’t really extend to emotion and motivation – the other
elements in what Hilgard (Hilgard,
1980), echoing Kant (and, for that matter, Plato)
called the trilogy of
mind. Accordingly,
the cognitive revolution of 1956-1967 was quickly followed by
what I have called the affective
counterrevolution, in which some psychologists asserted
that emotion deserved at least equal time.
M&K’s chapter on emotion began with an
extensive discussion of emotional development, and then turned
to a discussion of fear (the model system for studying emotion
at the time) and other negative emotions, like anger, conflict,
and frustration. After
detailing the role of the autonomic nervous system in emotional
arousal, they discussed the prevailing various theories of
emotion, including the James-Lange theory (James, 1884, 1890/1980),
Cannon’s (Cannon, 1927)
hypothalamic theory, and Schachter and Singer’s (Schachter & Singer, 1962) cognitive theory,
without taking sides among them.
In the wake of the cognitive revolution,
the dominant approach to emotion was, naturally, through
cognition: your emotional state was determined by your
perception of the conditions under which you felt
physiologically aroused. Put
bluntly, you don’t really
feel angry, you just think
you do. And if the
circumstances were right, the same undifferentiated state of
autonomic arousal, roughly analogous to what Cannon had in mind,
would be experienced as anger or happiness. The milestone in the
affective counterrevolution was a debate between Richard Lazarus
and Robert Zajonc about the independence of emotion from
cognition (Lazarus, 1981, 1982,
1984; Zajonc, 1980, 1984) in which Zajonc actually
asserted the primacy of affect – that a reflex-like,
generalized, positive or negative emotional reaction precedes
cognitive analysis. Similarly,
emotion researchers asserted the need for an interdisciplinary
affective neuroscience, modeled on but independent of cognitive
neuroscientists (Davidson, 2000;
Panksepp, 1992).
While (sometimes grudgingly)
acknowledging that cognitive restructuring can regulate emotion,
the dominant theory now is that emotion is substantially
independent of cognition, generated by a brain module, or better
system, in a manner close to that envisioned by Cannon (LeDoux, 1995, 2000). And there is not just
one brain system for emotion, but – in line with the
neuroscientific doctrine of modularity – a large number of such
modules, one for each emotion.
The failure to find differential physiological correlates
of the various emotions, which had been the thrust of Cannon’s
critique of the James-Lange theory, occurred because researchers
were looking in the wrong place.
The correlates were not to be found in the autonomic
nervous system, but rather in the skeletal musculature – and, in
particular, the face. Paul
Ekman proposed that evolution equipped us, and other mammals
with brains like ours, with at least six “basic emotions” (fear,
of course, plus joy, surprise, sadness, disgust, and anger),
each associated with a universally recognizable, hard-wired
signature facial expression (Ekman,
Friesen, & Ancoli, 1980). While the term “facial
expression” suggests that the emotion comes first, and causes
the expression, current theory holds that perception of the
facial expression creates the experience of emotion, or at least
enhances it, thus reversing the direction of causality. So, in a sense,
current views echo the James-Lange theory of the 19th
century. As the
French say, plus ca
change – except now we know a lot more about the neural
substrates of emotion. These
neural details have been worked out most comprehensively for
fear, but the framework is there for the other emotional states
as well.
The list of emotional states has also
gotten longer. At
the end of the 19th century, Wilhelm Wundt had argued
that there were just two kinds of emotion, pleasant and
unpleasant, varying only in strength. For the first part of
the 20th century, psychologists focused mostly on
fear, conflict, and frustration, and studied mostly in animals. Ekman’s gave us a more
differentiated list of qualitatively distinct “basic” emotions,
but his list accentuated the negative and the biologically
hard-wired. Most
recently, researchers have argued that the positive emotions go
beyond mere pleasure to include attachment-related emotions such as love, desire,
and sympathy; self-conscious
emotions such as embarrassment, shame, and pride; and epistemological and
self-transcendent emotions such as awe, ecstasy,
gratitude, interest, and confusion (Cowen & Keltner, 2017; Shiota et
al., 2017). It’s
not clear that these varieties of emotional experience are all
hard-wired by evolution, as Ekman argues his basic emotions are,
but the latest work certainly gives psychologists a richer
palette of emotions to work with.
So far, there has been no conative
counter-revolution similar to the affective counter-revolution,
but there have been important developments in the study of motivation nonetheless
– so much so that Higgins and others have claimed the status of
a separate interdisciplinary motivational science,
complementing cognitive and affective science (Higgins & Kruglanski, 2000). M&K’s chapter
focused on homeostatic regulation – as represented by
physiological drives like hunger, thirst, thermoregulation, and
pain. They also
discussed some “general” motives, such as drives for activity,
curiosity, manipulation, and affection. Here they gave
particular attention to the famous work of Harry Harlow on
“motherless monkeys”, and the importance of “contact comfort” (Blum, 2002; Harlow, 1953), as
well as less famous work that showed that rhesus monkeys (among
other animals) liked to examine things, and play with them, even
though the activity didn’t satisfy any primary physiological
drive – they did it, as it were, for the sheer hell of it.[4] In addition to innate
physiological drives like hunger, they also discussed
“secondary” drives which are learned through their association
with primary d drives. Money
is the classic example: we are motivated to earn money so that
we can buy food to eat in order to relieve hunger, and M&K
discussed some experiments in which monkeys were trained to work
for tokens which they could exchange for food. Another example is
fear conditioning, by which animals are motivated to escape or
avoid stimuli which have been associated with shock or other
painful stimuli.
Not surprisingly, since 1966 there
were developments on all of these fronts. For example, the
traditional account of hunger was that it was related to low
levels of glucose in the bloodstream. That’s true over the
short term, from meal to meal, but over longer terms eating is
regulated by levels of body fat.
It turns out that each of us has a “set point” – a level
of body fat that the body tries to maintain. If your accumulation
of body fat goes below your set point, you eat more; if it goes
above, you don’t eat so much (Powley
& Keesey, 1970).
The theory offers a better understanding of obesity and
weight regulation than we had before. We also understand
more about the role of cognitive, social, and cultural factors
in eating. For
example, amnesic patients will eat several meals in a row, so
long as it’s mealtime: even though their first meal satisfied
their immediate caloric needs, it’s time to eat, and they’ve
forgotten they’ve already eaten (Rozin,
Dow, Moscovitch, & Rajaram, 1998).
There have also been new developments
in secondary motivation. For
example, the “opponent-process” theory of acquired motivation,
originally inspired by a theory of color vision, holds that many
emotional states automatically evoke their hedonic opposites (Solomon & Corbit, 1974). So, for example the
pleasure that heroin and drugs is followed, when these drugs
wear off, not by a return to some hedonic neutral point but
rather the very unpleasant state of withdrawal. From this point of
view, drug addiction is not so much a matter of getting and
staying “high” as it is of avoiding the painful “crash” that
follows. Opponent-process
theory also offers a good account of nicotine addiction – as
well as new insights into effective treatments for addictive
disorders of all sorts.
At the same time, whole new domains of
research and theory have emerged, particularly with regard to
motivational aspects of personality and social interaction. M&K discussed
Murray’s classic theory of needs in their chapter on
“Personality”, but omitted empirical research in the Murray
tradition on the achievement motive by David McClelland and his
associates (McClelland,
Atkinson, Clark, & Lowell, 1953). Later research by
McClelland’s students on power (Winter,
1973) and affiliation/intimacy (McAdams, 1989) completed a
trilogy of research on what McClelland considered the three great social motives[5]. At the same time,
there was an increase in interest in intrinsic motivation – the
desire to engage in activities without promise or prospect of
reward. Early
indications that reward would actually undermine intrinsic
motivation (Lepper, Greene,
& Nisbett, 1973) led to a more subtle distinction
between the controlling and informational properties of rewards
(Harackiewicz, Manderlink, &
Sansone, 1984), and a better appreciation about how
extrinsic and intrinsic motives interact in goal-directed
behavior (Deci & Ryan,
2000). This
work has considerable practical importance, as insights from the
laboratory, confirmed by carefully controlled field research,
have shown us how to enhance student interest and performance in
STEM fields and other topics, including in minority and
first-generation students (Harackiewicz
& Hulleman, 2010; Harackiewicz, Smith, & Priniski,
2016).
There wasn’t, of course, any chapter
on consciousness in
M&K: “consciousness” wasn’t even in the index. In 1966, it was hard
enough to get psychologists talking about cognition, much less
emotion and motivation, as opposed to behavior. The very term, never
mind “the unconscious”, had been banished from psychological
discourse by behaviorist doctrine.
With the Cognitive Revolution, studies of attention,
short-term memory, and mental imagery created a way for
psychologists to talk about consciousness again – mostly without
actually using the term. In
1969, Charles Tart (Tart, 1969)
published a landmark anthology on Altered States of
Consciousness, collecting reports on sleep, dreams,
meditation, and psychedelic drugs.[6]
At about the same time, a number of
research lines converged to give revive interest in unconscious
mental life (Kihlstrom, 1987). Psychologists drew a
distinction between some complex mental processes operated
automatically, outside conscious awareness and control. Neuropsychological
research discovered that the behavior of amnesic patients could
influenced by events that they could not remember: such
“implicit” memories were, in effect, unconscious. Other research gave
new life to the concept of subliminal perception. And, finally, subjects
experiencing hypnotic analgesia or amnesia appeared to divide
consciousness, so that they were not aware of certain percepts
and memories that would otherwise be accessible to them.
Some theorists claimed that all this
research validated Freud’s notions concerning the roots of
neurosis in unconscious memories and desires. But the view of
unconscious mental life offered by studies of “the cognitive
unconscious” was quite different from Freud’s view of seething,
sexual and aggressive “Monsters from the Id” (to quote a phrase
from Forbidden Planet,
one of my favorite movies.
To take a phrase from President George H.W. Bush, the
unconscious revealed by modern scientific psychology was “kinder
and gentler” – and more adaptive – than that.
Personality
and Social Interaction
In 1966, however, Freudian
psychoanalysis was still an important theory of personality and
psychopathology. M&K
devoted three big chapters, more than 100 pages, to various
aspects of personality. Two of these chapters
dealt with various aspects of psychological testing – the
measurement of individual differences in intelligence (IQ),
personality traits, and social attitudes. To be honest, this
part of social psychology hasn’t changed very much. The statistical
methods have gotten more sophisticated, and the advent of
high-speed computers have made it easier to do more complex
“multivariate” analyses that go beyond simple correlations, but
the basic principles of psychological assessment -- reliability,
validity, and the like -- remain unchanged.
The big developments have been in
theory. One way or
another, M&K focused on Freudian psychoanalysis – which,
admittedly, was the most interesting theory of personality
around at the time. The
big thing in psychoanalysis is conflict, and M&K spent a lot
of time on animal studies of the various kinds of conflict and
its resolution – a line of research by Neal Miller and his
associates at Yale (Dollard,
Doob, Miller, Mowrer, & Sears, 1939), among others,
that was inspired by psychoanalysis and intended to connect the
laboratory and the clinic.
There was also an extensive discussion of repression and
other Freudian defense mechanisms, and “neo-Freudian” theories
that tried to move beyond sex and aggression. We still teach Freud
in the introductory course, as he is taught in mid-level courses
on personality, but that is mostly as a contribution to cultural
literacy. Freud got
some things right in the abstract, but he got every detail wrong
– worse performance, one of my colleagues (I forget who)
remarked, than you’d expect by chance! Now, the dominant view
of personality is focused on psychometrics, not psychoanalysis,
and is centered on “The Big Five” personality traits:
neuroticism, extraversion, agreeableness, conscientiousness, and
openness to experience (Goldberg,
1981; John & Srivastava, 1999; Norman, 1963). There is a passing
reference to The Big Five in M&K (though they don’t call it
that), but it wasn’t until the late 60s that personality
research really focused on the idea that pretty much everything
we know about an individual’s personality can be summarized in
the answers to five questions: Is s/he Crazy? Outgoing? Friendly? Trustworthy? Interesting? (I call them “The Five
Blind Date Questions”).
Another big development has been in
the assessment of personality.
M&K devoted most of their discussion of psychological
measurement to intelligence testing, and spent relatively little
time on personality questionnaires like the Minnesota
Multiphasic Personality Inventory (MMPI) and “projective”
techniques such as the Rorschach (inkblot) test and the Thematic
Apperception Test (TAT). Projective
techniques have now fallen by the wayside, along with the rest
of the Freudian-psychoanalytic apparatus, except in the
assessment of human motivation, where variants on the TAT have
been introduced with far more rigorous standards for
administration and interpretation.
The MMPI, too, has pretty much disappeared, replaced by a
new generation of questionnaires, much improved
psychometrically, that focus on The Big Five.
M&K devoted two chapters to social
psychology, including a whole chapter on attitude
assessment and change. Here,
perhaps not surprisingly (they were physiological psychologists,
after all) M&K were a little out of step with the field,
because they described very little experimental work,
focusing instead on observational studies that seem more like
sociology than psychology.
They did discuss the classic studies of conformity by
Muzafer Sherif (Sherif, 1936)
and Solomon Asch (Asch, 1956),
but there was no mention of Milgram’s (Milgram, 1963) revolutionary
study of obedience to authority, which launched a sort of
“golden age” of experimental research on interpersonal and group
processes. There
was some treatment of Festinger’s (Festinger, 1957), but very
little on persuasion and attitude change. All of that was to
come in the future (Cialdini,
1984; McGuire, 1986).
Also in the future was the “cognitive
revolution” in social psychology.
Recall that this major paradigm shift in psychology in
general began in 1956, and was consolidated in 1967 – the very
year in which M&K’s third edition appeared. And that was also the
year in which the cognitive revolution hit social psychology. Before that,
experimental social psychology had been very much a psychology
of the situation, examining the influence of the physical and
social environment on the individual’s behavior. Situationism was
exemplified by Milgram’s study of obedience to authority: if an
authority figure was present in the environment, people obeyed
in an almost reflex-like fashion.
But in 1968, John Darley and Bibb Latane (Darley & Latane, 1968)
published a study of bystander intervention which showed that
helping behavior depended on the individual’s interpretation of the
situation. Helping
occurred if the individual construed the situation as an
emergency, if he thought he could help, if he believed that
there were others who were in a better position to help, and so
on. It wasn’t the situation, defined
objectively (as the behaviorists might have done) that
controlled behavior; it was the individual’s subjective perception of the
situation that mattered. And
at this point social psychology got thoroughly cognitive,
leading to a whole array of courses, textbooks, and journals
devoted to social cognition: how people perceived, remember, and
think about other people, themselves, and the social situations
in which they met (Fiske &
Taylor, 1991; Higgins, Zanna, & Herman, 1981).
For some psychologists, however, the
cognitive approach to social interaction was too coldly rational
and calculating. This
led to what I have called the affective counterrevolution
in social psychology, which took off from the study of attitudes
– which, after all, are tendencies to like or dislike various
things. Thoughts
aren’t all that matters: feelings matter too. And just as the
cognitive perspective filtered over from experimental to social
psychology, the affective counterrevolution spilled over from
social psychology to psychology in general, so that we now have
something that we never had before: a full-fledged field
encompassing the gamut of emotional life, including positive
emotions, and social emotions – not just fear and other
affective states deeply rooted in biology (Cowen & Keltner, 2017; Ric,
Niedenthal, & Silvia Krauth-Gruber, 2012; Shiota et al.,
2017).
M&K gave personality and social
psychology separate chapters – and, indeed, for most of its
history the field treated these topics as separate and
independent (in one prominent university, the personality and
social psychology faculty were even housed in separate
buildings!). The
psychology of personality was focused on personality traits and
other internal dispositions, like The Big Five, and social
psychology was focused on external situational influences. But beginning in the
late 1960s, this separation began to be dissolved. First, Walter Mischel
undertook a vigorous, and hard-hitting, critique of the
traditional psychology of personality (Mischel, 1968). It turned out, for
example, that social behavior isn’t nearly as stable across
time, and as consistent across situations, as was implied by the
traditional doctrine of personality traits; nor, for that matter
was it easy to predict what an individual would do in a
particular situation, given knowledge of his general traits as
assessed by personality questionnaires. To the contrary,
Mischel argued that situational influences were more powerful
than personal ones, leading some social psychologists to
articulate an opposing doctrine of situationism that was closely
tied to the behaviorism of John B. Watson and B.F. Skinner (Zimbardo, 1999).
Mischel’s critique gave rise to what
might be thought of as a quintessentially masculine “battle of
the correlation coefficients” to see whose was bigger: the
personality psychologist’s correlation between traits and
behavior, or the social psychologist’s correlation between
situational variables and behavior (Epstein, 1983; Kenrick & Funder,
1988; Ross & Nisbett, 1991). Like most such
battles, this debate between “the person” and “the situation”
was stupid and pointless. In
the first place, Mischel meant the psychological
situation, as it was construed by the individual, and the
percepts, memories, and thoughts involved in that construal
belonged inside the person, not in the outside situation. In the second place,
empirically, nobody won: it turned out that the biggest
influence on behavior came from the interaction of trait
and situational variables.
I still cringe when I remember the reaction of my first
wife when I brought this insight home from the office: different people react
differently to different situations. But actually this
doctrine of interactionism was more profound than that: it said
that people construct the
situations to which they respond (Bowers, 1973). Just as the perceived
situation is a part of the person, so the person is part of the
situation to which he or she responds: you can’t separate them.
More recently, we have come to a
better understanding of how this person-situation interaction
takes place (Kihlstrom, 2013). People evoke changes
in the situation by their mere presence in it: infants, fresh
out of the womb, evoke different behavior from other people
depending on they have been identified as boys or girls: just
the knowledge of their gender changes the situation that is
imposed on them. Later
on, people choose to put themselves in one situation or another:
choosing to go to one college, as opposed to another effectively
puts you one situation as opposed to another. People who have been
thrust into a situation not of their own choosing can still
change it by their overt behavior: you can liven up a dull party
by putting a lampshade on your head and dancing on top of the
coffee table. And
even if their public behavior is constrained, people can change
how they think about the situation they’re in: root canals
become a lot more tolerable if you think of them as “saving
teeth” rather than “getting rid of rotting teeth”.
Traditionally,
the
person-situation debate was framed in terms of a unidirectional
view of causation: which is the stronger cause of behavior, the
person or the situation. even
the doctrine of interactionism was unidirectional: whether
through evocation, selection, behavioral manipulation, or
cognitive transformation, the person was a cause of the
situation. But then
Albert Bandura announced yet another doctrine, of reciprocal
determinism: causality goes in both directions. The person engages in
some behavior, but then the behavior feeds back to change the
person; the situation elicits some behavior, and that behavior
alters, or reinforces, the situation; and so on. In other words, the
person, the situation, and behavior together constitute a
dynamic system in which each element is the cause, and the
effect, of the other two. This
is a much different view of causality than was depicted in
M&K. It
complicates the science of psychology, not least with respect to
statistical analysis of experimental outcomes, but it is truer
to what actually happens.
M&K began their chapter on group
processes with a discussion of cultural influences on behavior,
and in this they were highly prescient: a major trend in social
psychology, especially over the (Nisbett,
2003). Partly
this trend reflects the unique status of psychology as both a
biological science, whose observer-independent principles apply
to all individuals, always and everywhere, and a social science,
whose observer-dependent phenomena exist only with respect to an
individual’s (or group’s) attitudes and intentionality (J. R. Searle, 1995). Consider, for example,
the nature of money: with fiat currency, a dollar bill is worth
a dollar only because we say it is; and even if the dollar was
tied to the gold standard, that standard is a human choice, and
we could just as well have chosen silver, or platinum, or some
other commodity, such as (to take examples from early American
history) wampum or beaver pelts.
Cultural psychology hypothesizes that even the basic
principles of mental life and behavior may be different,
depending on where you live.
A great deal of contemporary cultural
psychology is focused on differences between Americans and
Chinese and Japanese, on the other. For example, it has
been argued that Western culture fosters individualism and
independence, while Eastern culture fosters collectivism and
interdependence. To
be honest, some of this work seems more than a little
opportunistic: if you’ve got a Japanese graduate student,
injecting “culture” into your work is an easy way to score a
trip or two to Japan. And
some of it smacks of Orientalism (think of the Kipling’s “Ballad
of East and West”). In
the end, we’re probably more alike than we are different, and
the variability within cultural groups is almost certainly
greater than the variability between them. At the same time,
immigration is making the United States and Western Europe
increasingly diverse, and so it behooves us to understand
whatever it is that might keep us apart.
Development
Most of what’s covered in an
introductory psychology course pertains to adults (that is, what
doesn’t pertain to animal learning and physiology), raising the
question of the origins of mind, behavior, and personality. In their chapter on
development, M&K focused on maturation – the progressive
unfolding, in the child, or adult characteristics. This approach has its
merits, but it also tends to treat the child as a short, stupid
adult. An
alternative view of development was encouraged by Jean Piaget, a
Swiss psychologist who emphasized qualitative, not merely
quantitative, differences between childhood and adult cognition. Piaget argued that
cognitive development progressed through a series of stages,
each marked by a kind of milestone. For example, Piaget
argued that very young children, in what he called the stage of
sensory-motor operations, didn’t have a concept of object
permanence: if an object were out of sight, or out of reach, it
was also out of mind. Only
later do children acquire the ability to represent objects and
events mentally, in memory, and think about them even when
they’re not physically present in the immediate environment. Piaget’s announced his
theory in the 1930s, but it was only in the 1960s that it was
widely appreciated in American psychology (Flavell, 1967). M&K took notice,
but gave him only about two pages.
In the years hence, Piaget’s theory
came to dominate developmental psychology, and stage theories
proliferated wildly about almost everything – including, in
Elisabeth Kubler-Ross’s popular book On Death and Dying
(1969), the five stages of grief; and in the work of Maharishi
Mahesh Yogi (remember him?), a stage of “cosmic consciousness”
associated with the practice of Transcendental Meditation. More down to earth,
Piaget’s appreciation of the child’s unique intellectual
qualities appealed to educators, too, leading to the development
of “child-centered” educational policies. But it turned out that
Piaget overstated his case: for example, he argued that his
stages were universal, obligatory, stereotyped, and
irreversible: every child passed through each stage in exactly
the same sequence, each early stage serving as the prerequisite
for the next; the child moved wholesale from one stage to the
next, and once the shift occurred there was no going back. When these
propositions were tested by rigorously controlled research, it
turned out that they weren’t true, and a kind of cottage
industry developed in which psychologists tried to determine how
far they could push back the onset of each of Piaget’s stages . Not to exaggerate too
much, they eventually found hints of formal operations –
Piaget’s final stage – in infants fresh out of the womb.
In the aftermath of all of this
research, the pendulum has oscillated between Piaget-like
theories that emphasize qualitative differences between child
and adult thought, and theories that emphasize quantitative
differences. For
example, the earliest response to the critique of Piaget was the
idea that, over the course of development, children acquire
expertise in various domains – a proposal that seems to depict
the child as a short, stupid adult. The dominant view at
present is a “Theory Theory” which holds that, through
experimentation and learning, children
develop, refine, and reject theories of how the world operates
in its physical, biological, psychological, social, and personal
aspects (Gopnik, 2003; Gopnik,
Meltzoff, & Kuhl, 1999). This might also look
like a revival of the view of the child as a short, stupid
adult, and in some respects it is.
On the other hand, it portrays children as intrinsically
smart and curious. The
Theory Theory embraces Piaget’s view of the child as a naïve
scientist, actively engaged in figuring out how the world works. Development isn’t
something that just happens to the individual. There is a sort of
developmental corollary to the doctrine of interactionism, and
it is: the developing
child is both a target and an instigator of his or her own
development.
Piaget
focused on cognitive development, or the development of
intelligence broadly construed, but there have been big
advances in our understanding of personality development as
well. Many of
these have come from behavior genetics, and in particular the
twin-study method, which compares identical (monozygotic, MZ)
and fraternal dizygotic, DZ) twins on various aspects of
personality and social behavior.
The standard argument is that, to the extent that a
trait is inherited, MZ twins should be more alike than DZ
twins. That’s
true, but it’s also true that, to the extent that MZ twins are
different, those
differences must be due to differences in the environment. And, in fact, we can
distinguish between two different types of environmental
influence. There
is the shared
environment -- what siblings have in common by virtue of
having the same parents, living in the same household in the
same neighborhood, etc. And
there is the nonshared
environment -- what differentiates siblings form each
other by virtue of ordinal position in the family (firstborn
vs. latterborn), having different teachers, or running in
different circles of friends.
Behavior-genetic analyses of personality have yielded
two surprises. First,
there is a substantial genetic contribution to individual
differences in personality, amounting to perhaps 40% of
population variance. The
rest is due to environmental influences, but here’s the second
surprise: the vast proportion environmental contribution to
individual differences in personality – amounting to more
than half of the total variance -- comes from the nonshared
environment. Family
influence has remarkably little effect on personality
development (J.R. Harris,
1995; Judith Rich Harris, 1999; J.R. Harris, 2006). The uniqueness of
individual personality is due to the contingencies of his or
her existence: the unique environment each of us lives in, and
the unique experiences each of us have had. As I put it to my
class: the doctrine of interactionism has a developmental
correlate: in a very real sense, each and every child is born
to different parents, raised in a different family, lives in
a different neighborhood, attends a different school, and
worships in a different church.
Psychopathology
and Psychotherapy
M&K provided two chapters devoted
to what was then often called “abnormal psychology”. Their first chapter
defined various syndromes of neurosis, psychosis, personality
disorders, and the like along with case vignettes, and here a
great deal has changed (Kihlstrom,
2002). For
one thing, psychiatric diagnosis has become much more objective. The first edition of
the Diagnostic and
Statistical Manual for Mental Disorders (DSM), published by the
American Psychiatric Association in 1952, listed the various
syndromes, but gave psychiatrists and clinical psychologists
very little guidance as to how diagnoses were actually to be
made. The same was
true for the second edition, published in 1968, the year after
M&K’s 3e. But
beginning in 1980, the third and subsequent editions of DSM were accompanied by
rules that were intended to make diagnosis more reliable. For example, according
to the fifth and latest edition of DSM, in order to
receive a diagnosis of schizophrenia, a patient must present at
least two characteristic symptoms, such as hallucinations or
delusions. There
has also been a marked proliferation of psychiatric syndromes. By one count, there
were 128 separate diagnoses listed in DSM-I, and 541 in DSM-5, with more
syndromes being proposed every day, it seems, such as
pre-menstrual dysphoric disorder and internet addiction
disorder. On a more
serious note, autism (now autism spectrum disorder) entered the
diagnostic nosology with DSM-III
(1980), as did attention-deficit hyperactivity disorder (ADHD). Manic-depressive
illness is now called “bipolar disorder”. One important category
has dropped out of the manual, however: homosexuality, listed as
a “sexual deviation” in DSM-I
(and M&K), was removed from DSM-II in 1973 after
cultural change, and intense political campaign by the gay
community and its professional supporters, prompted serious
reconsideration by psychiatric authorities.
More changes are in the works. Whereas the current
diagnostic system is based on more or less discrete categories,
there is a movement to employ continuous dimensions instead. More critical,
however, is a likely shift in the way diagnoses are made. Up to now, diagnosis
has been based mostly on presenting symptoms, such as anxiety,
depression, or hallucinations.
But reflecting trends toward the biologization of
psychiatry (a topic to which I’ll return shortly), there is now
a movement to base classification on biological signs. Instead of being
diagnosed on the basis of debilitating, high levels of
unwarranted fear, anxiety disorder would be based, in large
part, on the presence of certain genes, or high levels of
cortisol, abnormal activity of the pituitary gland, or
malfunctioning in the bed nucleus of the stria terminalis in the
brain. This puts
the diagnosis of mental illness on the same physical basis as
other kinds of medical diagnosis by redefining mental illnesses
as brain diseases. While
it’s true that the brain is the biological basis of mental life,
such a move effectively leaves out the mental, which just…
seems…wrong – like (to use a phrase I got from Noam Chomsky)
throwing out the baby but keeping the bathwater. We’ll see how this
turns out.
M&K had little to say about
experimental psychopathology – that is, the use of concepts and
methods from the psychological laboratory to understand mental
illness. Experimental
psychopathology has a long history, going back almost to the
origins of scientific psychology itself (Hunt & Cofer, 1944; Kihlstrom,
2002; Kihlstrom & McGlynn, 1991; Zvolensky, Lejuez,
Stuart, & Curtin, 2001), but it really began to
pick up steam in the late 1960s (Chapman
& Chapman, 1973; Kimmel, 1971) – too late to be
included in M&K.
M&K’s discussion of the treatment
of mental illness covered both psychiatric drugs, chiefly
tranquilizers, and various forms of psychotherapy, including
psychoanalysis (still au
courant) and behavior therapy – a set of techniques based
on classical and instrumental conditioning, first introduced by
Joseph Wolpe in 1958. Again,
much has changed since then.
M&K’s discussion of psychotherapy focused mostly on
psychoanalysis, which was (and perhaps still is) the most
popular and culturally visible form of therapy at the time. They also briefly
discussed a provocative 1952 study by Hans Eysenck, a British
psychologist, which seemed to show that psychotherapy – meaning
mostly psychoanalysis – just didn’t work better than leaving
patients to recover on their own.
Beginning in the late 1950s, however, Joseph Wolpe (Wolpe, 1958)and others
introduced new forms of treatment, collectively known as
behavior therapy, which employed classical and instrumental
conditioning techniques to change the behavior (phobic
avoidance, obsessive thinking) of neurotic patients. Some forms of behavior
therapy, such as the token economies which reinforced behavior
change (Ayllon & Azrin,
1968), proved useful in the management of chronic
schizophrenia. As
their name implies, the first generation of behavior therapists
were behaviorists,
who generally abjured talk of mental states, mental illness, and
the like. Symptoms
were behaviors, and behaviors could be change by learning. But the cognitive
revolution came to psychotherapy, as well, and in 1967 Aaron
“Tim” Beck introduced cognitive therapy for depression (Beck, 1967). Beck, a psychiatrist
who had initially trained as a psychoanalyst, but who found the
Freudian conception of depression completely wrong-headed,
argued that the negative emotions characteristic of depression
were caused by “depressogenic” thoughts – ideas about oneself,
other, and the world that, if you harbored them, would make you
depressed, too. And
Beck showed that depression could be treated effectively by
changing these patterns of thought. Now we have a whole
host of new treatments, collectively known as
cognitive-behavioral therapy, which focus patients on the here
and now, rather than the there and then of Freudian theory. And these treatments
work: updates of Eysenck’s study, using vastly superior
methodology modeled on the randomized designs employed in drug
trials, repeatedly show that patients treated with various forms
of cognitive-behavioral therapy do better than waitlisted
controls. Psychoanalysis
and other forms of psychodynamic therapy “work” too, in that
sense, but by any standard cognitive-behavioral treatments work
better, more quickly, and last longer. They have become the
gold standard of psychotherapy.
As anyone who has left the television
on during dinner hour can attest, a vast panoply of drugs is now
available for the treatment of mental illness – constituting
what has become known as a “pharmaceutical revolution” in
psychiatry. Many of
these, such as the “selective serotonin reuptake inhibitors”
prescribed for depression, appear to go beyond the mere
tranquilizers, such as Valium, Librium, and Thorazine, that were
available in the 1950s and 1960s, and hold themselves out to be
specific treatments for biochemical abnormalities. On the other hand,
some critics have argued, based on pretty good data, that even
these new drugs are heavily contaminated by placebo effects (Kirsch & Sapirstein, 1999). The fact is, we still
don’t know much about how these drugs work. Nevertheless, the
search for new psychiatric drugs continues apace. But whatever the next
generation of psychiatric drugs brings us, the best evidence
indicates that the combination of drugs and psychotherapy is
better than either one alone – drugs for immediate relief,
therapy for long-lasting effects.
As the old adage says: if you give a man a fish, he eats
for a day; if you teach a man to fish, he eats for life. Active
cognitive-behavioral psychotherapy teaches patients to fish.
Applied
Psychology
The treatments for mental illness bring us naturally to
the question of other applications of the basic science of
psychology. M&K
offered a chapter on “Psychology in Industry”, showing how
psychological principles, mostly derived from social psychology,
could be employed in improving employee selection, job
satisfaction, and management.
This is now such a big business that industrial and
organizational psychology comprises a large component in
business school (where the professors earn a lot more money than
their counterparts in psychology departments). And psychology has
made important contributions to public policy as well. To take a salient
example, the “heuristics and biases” movement in the psychology
of judgment and decision-making led to the proposal that
governments and other organizations “nudge” their members into
making decisions that are in their own best interests (Benartzi et al., 2017). Left on their own to
“opt in”, people might not save sufficiently for retirement; but
if retirement savings are made automatic, allowing workers to
“opt out”, many more people participate, at higher levels, than
would otherwise be the case.
Similar findings have been obtained in other domains,
such as health insurance and organ donation.
The principles of scientific psychology, derived from
basic laboratory research have found wide application in other
domains of everyday life. The
psychology of learning is of obvious importance to education,
at all levels: we know how people can learn most efficiently,
and remember more effectively what they have learned (Bjork, Dunlosky, & Kornell,
2013; Dunlosky, Rawson, Marsh, Nathan, & Willingham, 2013;
Lee & Anderson, 2013). Advances in
psycholinguistics have, finally, taught us the best way to teach
children to read (hint: it involves phonics) (Castles, Rastle, & Nation, 2018;
Treiman, 2018). And
beyond cognitive psychology, social psychologists have helped us
to better understand how to motivate students to undertake
difficult subjects – understanding that is already helping
address the underrepresentation of minorities in STEM fields (Harackiewicz, 2018; Reber, Canning,
& Harackiewicz, 2018; Sansone & Harackiewicz, 2000).
The same sorts of principles find applications in healthcare. An important key to
health is health behavior.
How people behave with respect to health and illness will
depend, in large part, on how they think about health and
illness (Armitage & Conner,
2000; Lau & Hartman, 1983; Leventhal & Diefenbach,
1990; Leventhal, Meyer, & Nerenz, 1980):
prevention: prevention regimes can be arduous, and people must
be motivated to engage in them – this is the problem of
compliance or, less pejoratively, adherence (Christensen & Johnson, 2002;
Gochman, 1997; Myers & Midence, 1998). (For that matter,
physicians must adhere to treatment guidelines.) Overweight people need
to diet and exercise. Women
must be motivated to perform breast self-examinations, get
regular mammograms and pap tests.
Both men and women need to be checked for colon cancer –
even if it involves the occasional colonoscopy. In an age of HIV/AIDS,
populations at risk must be motivated to refrain from risky
sexual behaviors, or at least wear condoms or other protection
during them. If
illness strikes, the treatment regimes can also be onerous. Diabetics must take
multiple blood-sugar readings every day, and then inject
themselves with insulin. People
who have had a heart attack must faithfully attend appointments
for rehabilitation. Pharmacologists
can concoct pills for lots of illnesses: not to demean it, but
that is strictly a matter of biology. But then you’ve got to
get people to take the pills: and that’s a matter for
psychology.
Fifty Years is a Long
Time
I want to
be clear that, in outlining the differences between what we knew
then and what we know now, I intend no criticism of Morgan and
King, expressed or implied.
Edmonston chose their textbook was chosen precisely
because it was up-to-date, representing our best understanding
of mind and behavior at the time.
The point is that, beginning in the late 1960s, pretty
much everything about that understanding changed. In the space of 50
years, psychological research and theory have changed
completely. And
that’s one of the things that has made psychology such a great
science – there is so much to be learned, and in the space of a
single professional lifetime – mine, for instance – one can
witness not one, or two, but three or maybe more revolutions in
our understanding of mind and behavior: the cognitive
revolution, overthrowing behaviorism and returning mind to the
center of psychology; the affective counterrevolution, reminding
psychologists of the importance of emotion and motivation, and
acting as a “wet, warm” corrective to “cold, dry” rationality;
and the neuroscientific revolution, in which biological
psychologists made use of psychological methods and theories to
unravel the biological bases of mental life. And have the
opportunity to share some of these insights with a new
generation of students, like you.
Because there’s still so much left to learn about how the
mind works, and the role mind and brain play in behavior.
References
Armitage, C. J.,
& Conner, M. (2000). Social Cognition Models and Health
Behavior: A Structured Review. Psychology & health, 15(2),
173.
Asch, S. E. (1956).
Studies of independence and conformity: I. A minority of one
against a unanimous majority. Psychological Monographs,
70(9), 70.
Aslin, R. N., &
Newport, E. L. (2012). Statistical learning: From acquiring
specific items to forming general rules. Current Directions in
Psychological Science, 21(3), 170-176.
Atkinson, R. C.,
& Shiffrin, R. M. (1968). Human memory: A proposed system
and its control processes. In K. W. Spence & J. T. Spence
(Eds.), The psychology of
learning and motivation (Vol. 2, pp. 89-105). New York:
Academic Press.
Ayllon, T., &
Azrin, N. H. (1968). The
token economy: A motivational system for therapy and
rehabilitation. New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Bandura, A. (1962).
Social learning through imitation. In M. R. Jones (Ed.), Nebraska Symposium on
Motivation. Lincoln: University of Nebraska Press.
Barlsalou, L. (2008).
Grounded cognition. Annual
Review of Psychology, 59, 617-645.
Beck, A. T. (1967). Depression: Causes and
treatment. Philadelphia: University of Pennsylvania Press.
Benartzi, S.,
Beshears, J., Milkman, K. L., Sunstein, C. R., Thaler, R. H.,
Shankar, M., . . . Galing, S. (2017). Should Governments Invest
More in Nudging? Psychological
Science, 28(8), 1041 - 1055. doi: https://doi.org/10.1177/0956797617702501
Bjork, R. A.,
Dunlosky, J., & Kornell, N. (2013). Self-regulated learning:
Beliefs, techniques,and illusions. Annual Review of
Psychology, 64, 417-444.
Blum, D. (2002). Love at Goon Park: Harry
Harlow and the Science of Affection. Buffalo, N.Y.:
Perseus.
Bowers, K. S. (1973).
Situationism in psychology -- Analysis and a critique. Psychological Review, 80,
307-336. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0035592
Bowers, K. S.,
Regehr, G., Balthazard, C., & Parker, K. (1990). Intuition
in the context of discovery. Cognitive Psychology, 22,
72-110.
Buss, D. M. (2009).
The great struggles of life: Darwin and the emergence of
evolutionary psychology. American
Psychologist, 64, 140-148.
Cannon, W. B. (1927).
The James-Lange theory of emotions: A critical examination and
an alternative theory. American
Journal of
Psychology, 39, 106-124.
Castles, A., Rastle,
K., & Nation, K. (2018). Ending the reading wars:
Reading acquisition from novice to expert. Psychological Science in
the Public Interest, 19(1).
Chapman, L. J., &
Chapman, J. P. (1973). Disordered
thought in schizophrenia. Englewood Cliffs, N.J.:
Prentice-Hall.
Chomsky, N. (1957). Syntactic structures.
The Hague: Mouton.
Chomsky, N. (1959).
Review of Verbal Behavior
by B.F. Skinner. Language
& Speech, 35, 26-58.
Chomsky, N. (1972). Language and freedom.
New York: TriQuarterly.
Christensen, A. J.,
& Johnson, J. A. (2002). Patient Adherence With Medical
Treatment Regimens: An Interactive Approach. Current Directions in
Psychological Science, 11(3), 94-97.
Christian, B., &
Griffiths, T. A. (2016). Algorithms
to live by: The computer science of human decisions. New
York: Henry Holt.
Cialdini, R. B.
(1984). Influence: How
and why people agree to do things. New York: Quill.
Collings, V. B.
(1974). Human taste response as a function of locus of
stimulation on the tongue and soft palate. Perception &
Psychophysics, 16(1), 69-74.
Confer, J. C.,
Easton, J. A., Fleischman, D. S., Goetz, C. D., Lewis, D. M. G.,
Perilloux, C., & Buss, D. M. (2010). Evolutionary
psychology: Controversies, questions, prospects, and
limitations. American
Psychologist, 65, 110-126.
Cowen, A. S., &
Keltner, D. (2017). Self-report captures 27 distinct categories
of emotion bridged by continuous gradients. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, in press.
Cronbach, L. J.
(1957). The two disciplines of scientific psychology. American Psychologist, 12,
671-684.
Cumming, G. (2014).
The new statistics: Why and how. Psychological Science, 25,
7-29.
Darley, J. M., &
Latane, B. (1968). Bystander intervention in emergencies:
Diffusion of responsibility. Journal of Personality
& Social Psychology, 46, 991-1004.
Davidson, R. J.
(2000). Cognitive neuroscience needs affective neuroscience (and
vice versa). Brain &
Cognition, 42(1), 89-92.
Deci, E. L., &
Ryan, R. M. (2000). The “what” and “why” of goal pursuits: Human
needs and the self-determination of behavior. Psychological Inquiry, 11(4),
227-268.
Dollard, J., Doob, L.
W., Miller, N.E., Mowrer, O. H., & Sears, R. R. (1939). Frustration and aggression.
New Haven: Yale University Press.
Dunlosky, J., Rawson,
K. A., Marsh, E. J., Nathan, M. J., & Willingham, d. T.
(2013). Improving students' leraning with effective learning
techniques: Promising directions from cognitive and educational
psychology. Psychological
Science in the Public Interest, 14(1), 4-58.
Ekman, P., Friesen,
W. V., & Ancoli, S. (1980). Facial signs of emotional
experience. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 39, 1125-1134.
Epstein, S. (1983).
Aggregation and beyond: Some basic issues in the prediction of
behavior. Journal of
Personality, 51(3), 360-392.
Festinger, L. (1957).
A theory of cognitive
dissonance. Stanford, Ca.: Stanford University Press.
Fiske, S. T., &
Taylor, S. E. (1991). Social
cognition (2nd ed.). New York: Random House.
Flavell, J. (1967). The developmental
psychology of Jean Piaget. New York: Van Nostrand.
Garcia, J., Ervin,
F., & Koelling, R. (1966). Learning with prolonged delay of
reinforcement. Psychonomic
Science, 5, 121-122.
Gardner, H. (1985). The mind's new science : A
history of the cognitive revolution. New York: Basic
Books.
Gazzaniga, M. S.
(1998). The mind's past.
Berkeley: University of California Press.
Gazzaniga, M. S.,
Bogen, J. E., & Sperry, R. W. (1962). Some functional
effects of sectioning the cerebral commissures in man. Proceedings of the National
Academy of Sciences, 48, 1756-1769.
Gazzaniga, M. S.,
Ivry, R. B., & Mangun, G. R. (2014). Cognitive neuroscience: The
biology of the mind (4th ed.). New York: Norton.
Gibson, J. J. (1966).
The senses considered as
perceptual systems. Boston: Houghton Mifflin.
Gochman, D. (1997).
Adherence to and acceptance of regimens: General perspectives.
In D. Gochman (Ed.), Handbook
of health behavior research (Vol. 2, pp. 105-107). New
York: Plenum.
Goldberg, L. R.
(1981). Language and individual differences: The search for
universals in personality lexicons. In L. Wheeler (Ed.), Review of Personality &
Social Psychology (Vol. 2, pp. 141-165). Beverly Hills,
Ca.: Sage.
Gopnik, A. (2003).
The theory theory as an alternative to the innateness
hypothesis. In L. Antony & N. L. Hornstein (Eds.), Chomsky and His Critics.
New York: Basil Blackwell.
Gopnik, A., Meltzoff,
A. N., & Kuhl, P. M. (1999). The scientist in the crib:
What early learning tells us about the mind (Vol. Morrow):
New York.
Green, D. M., &
Swets, J. A. (1966). Signal
detection theory and psychophysics. New York: Wiley.
Greenwald, A. G.,
Draine, S. C., & Abrams, R. L. (1996). Three cognitive
markers of unconscious semantic activation. Science, 273,
1699-1702. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.273.5282.1699
Gregory, R. L.
(1970). The intelligent
eye. London,: Weidenfeld & Nicolson.
Harackiewicz, J. M.
(2018). Improving student outcomes in higher education: The
science of targeted intervention. Annual Review of
Psychology, 69, 409-435.
Harackiewicz, J. M.,
& Hulleman, C. S. (2010). The importance of interest: The
role of achievement goals and task values in promoting the
development of interest. Social
& Personality Psychology Compass, 4(1), 42-52.
Harackiewicz, J. M.,
Manderlink, G., & Sansone, C. (1984). Rewarding pinball
wizardry: Effects of evaluation and cue value on intrinsic
interest. Journal of
Personality and Social Psychology, 47, 287-300.
Harackiewicz, J. M.,
Smith, J. L., & Priniski, S. J. (2016). Interest matters:
The importance of promoting interest in education. Policy Insights from the
Behavioral and Brain Sciences, 3(2), 220-227.
Harlow, H. F. (1953).
Mice, monkeys, men, and motives. Psychological Review, 60,
23-32.
Harris, C. R. (2003).
A Review of Sex Differences in Sexual Jealousy, Including
Self-Report Data, Psychophysiological Responses, Interpersonal
Violence, and Morbid Jealousy. Personality and Social
Psychology Review, 7(2), 102-128.
Harris, J. R. (1995).
Where is the child's environment? A group socialization theory
of development. Psychological
Review, 102(3), 458-489.
Harris, J. R. (1999).
The Nurture assumption:
Why children turn out the way they do (pb ed.). New York:
Touchstone.
Harris, J. R. (2006).
No two alike: Human nature
and human individuality. New York: Norton.
Hastie, R., &
Dawes, R. M. (2010). Rational
choice in an uncertain world : The psychology of judgment and
decision making (2nd ed.). Thousand Oaks, Calif.: Sage.
Hecaen, H. (1962).
Clinical symptomatology in right and left hemispheric lesions.
In V. B. Mountcastle (Ed.), Interhemispheric lesions
and cerebral dominance (pp. 215-243). Baltimore: Johns
Hopkins University Press.
Higgins, E. T., &
Kruglanski, A. W. (Eds.). (2000). Motivational science:
Social and personality perspectives. New York: Psychology
Press.
Higgins, E. T.,
Zanna, M. P., & Herman, C. P. (Eds.). (1981). Social cognition: The
Ontario Symposium (Vol. 1). Hillsdale, N.J.: Erlbaum.
Hilgard, E. R.
(1980). The trilogy of mind: Cognition, affection, and conation.
Journal for the History
of the Behavioral Sciences, 16, 107-117. doi: https://doi.org/10.1002/1520-6696(198004)16:2<107::AID-JHBS2300160202>3.0.CO;2-Y
Hochberg, J. E.
(1978). Perception
(2d ed.). Englewood Cliffs, N.J.: Prentice-Hall.
Hubel, D. H., &
Wiesel, T. N. (1959). Receptive fields of single neurones in the
cat’s striate
cortex. Journal of Physiology, 148,
574-591.
Hull, C. L. (1920).
Quantitative aspects of the evolution of concepts: An
experimental study. Psychological
Monographs, 28(Whole No. 123).
Hunt, J. M., &
Cofer, C. N. (1944). Psychological deficit. In J. M. Hunt (Ed.),
Personality and the
behavior disorders (Vol. 2, pp. 971-1032). New York:
Ronald.
Hurvich, L. M., &
Jameson, D. (1957). An opponent-process theory of color vision.
Psychological Review, 64,
384-404.
James, W. (1884).
What is an emotion? Mind,
9, 188-205.
James, W.
(1890/1980). Principles
of Psychology. Cambridge, Ma.: Harvard University Press.
John, O. P., &
Srivastava, S. (1999). The Big Five Trait taxonomy: History,
measurement, and theoretical perspectives. In L. A. Pervin &
O. P. John (Eds.), Handbook
of personality: Theory and research (pp. 102-138). New
York: Guilford Press.
Jones, B. C., Hahn,
A. C., Fisher, C. I., Wang, H., Kandrik, M., Han, C., . . .
DeBruine, L. M. (2018). No Compelling Evidence That Preferences
for Facial Masculinity Track Changes in Women’s Hormonal Status.
Psychological Science, in
press.
Kay, K. N.,
Naselaris, T., Prenger, R. J., & Gallant, J. L. (2008).
Identifying natural images from human brain activity. Nature, 452, 352-355.
Kenrick, D. T., &
Funder, D. C. (1988). Profiting from controversy: Lessons from
the person-situation debate. American Psychologist, 43,
23.
Kihlstrom, J. F.
(1987). The cognitive unconscious. Science, 237(4821),
1445-1452. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.3629249
Kihlstrom, J. F.
(1996). Memory research: The convergence of theory and practice.
In D. Hermann, M. Johnson, C. McEvoy, C. Hertzog & P. Hertel
(Eds.), Basic and applied
memory: Theory in context (Vol. 1, pp. 5-25). Mahwah,
N.J.: Erlbaum.
Kihlstrom, J. F.
(2002). To honor Kraepelin...: From symptoms to pathology in the
diagnosis of mental illness. In L. E. Beutler & M. L. Malik
(Eds.), Alternatives to
the DSM (pp. 279-303). Washington, D.C.: American
Psychological Association.
Kihlstrom, J. F.
(2013). The person-situation interaction. In D. Carlston (Ed.),
Oxford handbook of social
cognition (pp. 786-805). New York: Oxford University
Press.
Kihlstrom, J. F.,
& Edmonston, W. E. (1971). Alterations in Consciousness in
Neutral Hypnosis: Distortions in Semantic Space. American Journal of
Clinical Hypnosis, 13(4), 243-248.
Kihlstrom, J. F.,
& McGlynn, S. M. (1991). Experimental research in clinical
psychology. In M. Hersen, A. E. Kazdin & A. S. Bellack
(Eds.), Clinical
psychology handbook (2nd ed.). (2nd ed., pp. 239-257). New
York: Pergamon Press, Inc.
Kihlstrom, J. F.,
Shames, V. A., & Dorfman, J. (1996). Intimations of memory
and thought. In L. M. Reder (Ed.), Implicit memory and
metacognition (pp. 1-23). Mahwah, N.J.: Erlbaum.
Kimmel, H. D. (Ed.).
(1971). Experimental
psychopathology: Recent research and theory. New York:
Academic Press.
Kirsch, I., &
Sapirstein, G. (1999). Listening to Prozac but hearing placebo:
A meta-analysis of antidepressant medications How expectancies shape
experience. (pp. 303-320). Washington, DC, USA: American
Psychological Association.
Krumhansl, C. L.
(1991). Music psychology: Tonal structures in perception and
memory Annual Review of
Psychology (pp. 277-303).
Krumhansl, C. L.
(2000). Rhythm and Pitch in Music Cognition. Psychological bulletin, 126(1),
159.
Krumhansl, C. L.
(2002). Music: A Link Between Cognition and Emotion. Current Directions in
Psychological Science, 11(2), 45-49.
Lau, R. R., &
Hartman, K. A. (1983). Common sense representations of common
ilnesses. Health
Psychology, 2, 167-185.
Lazarus, R. S.
(1981). A cognitivist's reply to Zajonc on emotion and
cognition. American
Psychologist, 36(2), 222-223.
Lazarus, R. S.
(1982). Thoughts on the relations between emotion and cognition.
American Psychologist, 37(9),
1019-1024.
Lazarus, R. S.
(1984). On the primacy of cognition. American Psychologist, 39(2),
124-129.
LeDoux, J. E. (1995).
Emotion: Clues from the brain. Annual Review of
Psychology, 46, 209-235.
LeDoux, J. E. (2000).
Emotion circuits in the brain. Annual Review of
Neuroscience, 23, 155-184.
Lee, H. S., &
Anderson, J. R. (2013). Student learning: What has instruction
got to do with it? Annual
Review of Psychology, 64, 445-469.
Lepper, M. R.,
Greene, D., & Nisbett, R. E. (1973). Undermining children's
intrinsic interest with extrinsic reward: a test of the
"overjustification" hypothesis. Journal of Personality
& Social Psychology, 28, 129-137.
Leventhal, H., &
Diefenbach, M. (1990). The active side of illness cognition. In
J. A. Skelton & R. T. Croyle (Eds.), Mental representation in
health and illness (pp. in press). New York:
Springer-Verlag.
Leventhal, H., Meyer,
D. E., & Nerenz, D. (1980). The common sense representation
of illness danger. In S. Rachman (Ed.), Medical Psychology
(Vol. 2, pp. in press). London: Pergamon Press.
Lewis, D. M. G.,
Al-Shawaf, L., Conroy-Beam, D., Asao, K., & Buss, D. M.
(2017). Evolutionary Psychology: A How-To Guide. American Psychologist, 72(4),
353-373.
Liberman, A. M.,
Cooper, F. S., Shankweiler, D. P., & Studdert-Kennedy, M.
(1967). Perception of the speech code. Psychological Review, 74,
431-461.
McAdams, D. P.
(1989). Intimacy: The
need to be close. New York, NY, US: Doubleday & Co.
McClelland, D. C.,
Atkinson, J. W., Clark, R. A., & Lowell, E. L. (Eds.).
(1953). The achievement
motive. East Norwalk, CT: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
McClintock, M. K.
(2000). Human Pheromones: Primers, Releasers, Signalers or
Modulators? In K. Wallen & J. E. Schneider (Eds.), Reproduction in Context
(pp. 355-420). Cambridge, MA: MIT Press.
McGuire, W. J.
(1986). The vicissitudes of attitudes and similar
representational constructs in twentieth century psychology. European Journal of Social
Psychology, 16, 89-130.
Milgram, S. (1963).
Behavioral Study of Obedience. Journal of Abnormal &
Social Psychology, 67(4), 371-378.
Miller, G. A. (2003).
The cognitive revolution: a historical perspective. Trends in Cognitive
Sciences, 7(3), 141-144.
Mineka, S., &
Kihlstrom, J. F. (1978). Unpredictable and uncontrollable
events: A new perspective on experimental neurosis. Journal of Abnormal
Psychology, 87(2), 256-271.
Mischel, W. (1968). Personality and assessment.
New York: Wiley.
Morgan, C. T., &
King, R. A. (1966). Introduction
to psychology (3rd ed.). New York: McGraw-Hill.
Myers, L. B., &
Midence, K. (Eds.). (1998). Adherence to treatment in
medical conditions. Amsterdam: Harwood.
Neisser, U. (1967). Cognitive psychology.
New York: Appleton-Century-Crofts.
Nemeroff, C. B.,
& Loosen, P. T. (Eds.). (1987). Handbook of Clinical
Psychoneuroendocrinology
New York: Guilford.
Newell, A., Shaw, J.
C., & Simon, H. A. (1958). Elements of a theory of human
problem solving. Psychological
Review, 65, 151-166.
Niedenthal, P. M.,
Barsalou, L. W., Winkielman, P., KrauthGruber, S., & Ric, F.
(2005). Embodiment in Attitudes, Social Perception, and Emotion.
Personality and Social
Psychology Review, 9(3), 184-211.
Nisbett, R. (2003). The Geography of Thought :
How Asians and Westerners Think Differently...and Why. New
York: Free Press.
Norman, W. T. (1963).
Toward an adequate taxonomy of personality attributes:
Replicated factor structure in peer nomination personality
ratings. Journal of
Abnormal and Social Psychology, 66, 574-583.
Orne, M. T. (1962).
On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: With
particular reference to demand characteristics and their
implications. American
Psychologist, 17, 776-783. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0043424
Palmer, S. E. (1999).
Vision science: photons to
phenomenology. Cambridge, Ma.: MIT Press.
Panksepp, J. (1992).
A critical role for "affective neuroscience" in resolving what
is basic about basic emotions. Psychological Review, 99(3),
554-560.
Pinker, S. (2007). The stuff of thought:
Language as a window into human nature, . New York:
Viking.
Pinker, S. M. (1994).
The language instinct: How
the mind creates language. New York: Morrow.
Powley, T. L., &
Keesey, R. E. (1970). Relationship of body weight to the lateral
hypothalamic feeding syndrome. Journal of Comparative and
Physiological Psychology, 70(1), 25-36. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0028390
Proffitt, D. R.
(2006). Embodied perception and the economy of action. Perspectives on
Psychological Science, 1(2), 110-122.
Proffitt, D. R.
(2013). An embodied approach to perception: by what units are
visual perceptions scaled? Perspectives on
Psychological Science, 8(4), 474-483.
Reber, R., Canning,
E. A., & Harackiewicz, J. M. (2018). Personalized education
to increase interest. Current
Directions in Psychological Science, 27(6), 449-454.
Ric, F., Niedenthal,
P. M., & Silvia Krauth-Gruber, S. (2012). Psychology of Emotion:
Interpersonal, Experiential, and Cognitive Approaches (2nd
ed.).
Rock, I. (1975). An introduction to
perception. New York: Macmillan.
Roediger, H. L.
(2000). Sir Frederic Charles Bartlett: Experimental and applied
psychologist. In G. A. Kimble & M. Wertheimer (Eds.), Portraits of pioneers in
psychology (Vol. 4, pp. in press). Mahwah, N.J.: Erlbaum.
Rosch, E. (1975).
Cognitive representations of semantic categories. Journal of Experimental
Psychology: General, 104, 192-233.
Rosenthal, R. (1963).
On the social psychology of the psychological experiment: The
experimenter's hypothesis as unintended determinant of
experimental results. American
Scientist, 51, 270-282.
Ross, L., &
Nisbett, R. E. (1991). The
person and the situation: Perspectives of social psychology.
New York: McGraw-Hill.
Rozin, P., Dow, s.,
Moscovitch, M., & Rajaram, S. (1998). What causes humans to
begin and end a meal: A role for memory for what has been eaten,
as evidened by a study of multiple meal eating in amnesic
patients. Psychological
Science, 9(5), 392-396.
Rozin, P., &
Kalat, J. W. (1971). Specific hungers and poison avoidance as
adaptive specializations of learning. Psychological Review, 78(6),
459-486. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0031878
Sansone, C., &
Harackiewicz, J. M. (Eds.). (2000). Intrinsic and Extrinsic
Motivation: The Search for Optimal Motivation and Performance.
San Diego: Academic Press.
Schachter, S., &
Singer, J. E. (1962). Cognitive, social, and physiological
determinants of emotional state. Psychological Review, 69,
379-399.
Scoville, W. B.,
& Milner, B. (1957). Loss of recent memory after bilateral
hippocampal lesions. Journal
of Neurology, Neurosurgery & Psychiatry, 20, 11-21.
Searle, J. R. (1995).
The construction of social
reality. New York: Free Press.
Searle, J. S. (1972).
Chomsky's revolution in linguistics. New York Review of Books(June
29).
Segerstrom, S. C.
(Ed.). (2012). Oxford
handbook of psychoneuroimmunology. New York: Oxford
University Press.
Seligman, M. E. P.
(1970). On the generality of the laws of learning. Psychological Review, 77(5),
406-418.
Seligman, M. E. P.,
Maier, S. F., & Solomon, R. L. (1971). Unpredictable and
uncontrollable aversive events. In F. R. Brush (Ed.), Aversive conditioning and
learning. New York: Academic Press.
Sherif, M. (1936). The psychology of social
norms. New York: Harper & Row.
Shiota, M. N.,
Campos, B., Oveis, C., Hertenstein, M. J., Simon-Thomas, E.,
& Keltner, D. (2017). Beyond happiness: Building a science
of discrete positive emotions. American Psychologist, 72(7),
617-643.
Simon, H. A. (1956).
Rational Choice and the Structure of the Environment. Psychological Review, 63(2),
129-138. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0042769
Solomon, R. L., &
Corbit, J. D. (1974). An opponent-process theory of motivation:
I. temporal dynamics of affect. Psychological Review, 81(2),
119-145. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/h0036128
Squire, L. R.,
Shimamura, A. P., & Amaral, D. G. (1989). Memory and the
hippocampus. In J. Byrne & W. Berry (Eds.), Neural models of plasticity
(pp. 208-239). New York: Academic.
Tart, C. T. (Ed.).
(1969). Altered States of
Consciousness: A Book of Readings. New York: Wiley.
Treiman, R. (2018).
What research tells us about reading instruction. Psychological Science in
the Public Interest, 19(1).
Tulving, E. (1972).
Episodic and semantic memory. In E. Tulving & W. Donaldson
(Eds.), Organization of
memory. New York: Academic Press.
Turkheimer, E.,
Pettersson, E., & Horn, e. E. (2014). A phenotypic null
hypothesis for the genetics of personality. Annual Review of
Psychology, 65, 515-540.
Turkheimer, E., &
Waldron, M. (2000). Nonshared Environment: A Theoretical,
Methodological, and Quantitative Review. Psychological bulletin, 126(1),
78.
Tversky, A., &
Kahneman, D. (1974). Judgment under uncertainty: heuristics and
biases. Science, 185,
1124-1131. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1126/science.185.4157.1124
Warrington, E. K.,
& Weiskrantz, L. (1968). New method of testing long-term
retention with special reference to amnesic patients. Nature, 217, 972-974.
Winograd, T. (1975).
Frame representations and the declarative/procedural
controversy. In D. Bobrow & A. Collins (Eds.), Representations and
understanding: Essays in cognitive science (pp. 185-212).
New York: Academic.
Winter, D. G. (1973).
The power motive. New
York: Free Press.
Wolpe, J. (1958). Psychotherapy by reciprocal
inhibition. Stanford, Ca.: Stanford University Press.
Yamaguchi, S. (1998).
Basic properties of umami and its effects in humans. PHYSIOLOGY & BEHAVIOR,
49, 833-841.
Zajonc, R. B. (1980).
Feeling and thinking: Preferences need no inferences. American Psychologist, 35,
151-175.
Zajonc, R. B. (1984).
On the primacy of affect. American
Psychologist, 39, 117-123.
Zimbardo, P. G.
(1999). Experimental social psychology: Behaviorism with minds
and matters. In A. Rodrigues & R. V. Levine (Eds.), Reflections on 100 years of
experimental social psychology (pp. 135-157). New York:
Basic Books.
Zvolensky, M. J.,
Lejuez, C. W., Stuart, G. L., & Curtin, J. J. (2001).
Experimental psychopathology in psychological science. Review of General
Psychology, 5, 371-381. doi: http://dx.doi.org/10.1037/1089-2680.5.4.371
[1]
Institutional psychology was so besotted with behaviorism,
and so hostile to any mention of internal mental states,
that some early cognitivists had to assert their
independence by establishing programs in “cognitive science”
(Gardner, 1985). In some respects,
cognitive science is broader than psychology, because it is
interested in the acquisition, representation,
transformation, and utilization of knowledge by brains,
machines, and societies as well as individual human minds. But in other
respects, cognitive science is narrower than psychology,
because psychology is concerned with emotion, motivation,
and action as well as cognition. A famous cognitive
neuroscientist has declared that “psychology is dead” (M.S Gazzaniga, 1998) (,
p. xi), and some psychologists prefer to call themselves
“cognitive scientists” or “cognitive neuroscientists”
instead. Psychology
departments have also sometimes re-labeled themselves – as,
for example, departments of brain and cognitive science
(e.g., MIT and Rochester).
But to the extent that these individuals and
institutions are interested in mental life, they’re still
operating as psychologists. Psychology is still where it all
comes together: where cognitive, emotional, and motivational
states processes generate the behavior of the individual
person.
[2]
I made use of Wallas’s analysis in my own research on
implicit or unconscious thought (Kihlstrom, Shames, &
Dorfman, 1996) In our view, intuition reflects the
unconscious influence of an idea on behavior, while insight
reflects the emergence of that idea into full phenomenal
awareness. I
first learned about Wallas in Intro, and I was reminded of
his theory when Kenneth S. Bowers revived research interest
in intuition by showing that subjects could identify which
of two problems was soluble, even though they did not know
what the solutions were (Bowers,
Regehr, Balthazard, & Parker, 1990).
[3]
I used this scheme in my senior honors thesis, in an attempt
to quantify alterations in consciousness during hypnosis (Kihlstrom & Edmonston, 1971). The idea was that
an altered state of consciousness would result in the
meaning ascribed to various concepts, as represented in
shifts in Osgood’s three-dimensional semantic space. And so it did. So that’s at least
two things of lasting importance that I carried out of Intro
and into my later career.
[4]
Another tale from 50 years ago: The requirements
for the psychology major at Colgate included a two-semester
“methods” sequence – a rarity in psychology majors nowadays. One of the units
was animal learning, taught by Nicholas Longo, a comparative
psychologist who studied conditioning in fish and
invertebrates, including octopus. In another
university, psychology majors might have gotten a rat or a
pigeon to train: I got a goldfish, and an apparatus in which
the fish could press a submerged paddle with its snout to
deliver a food reward in the form of a mealworm. Paddle-pressing
also turned on a light in the fish tank. We also ran a
control condition in which the food, but not the light, was
disconnected from the paddle.
Nevertheless, the fish kept pressing. Having read about
Harlow’s studies in M&K, I thought that this might be an
instance of what they called a generalized drive to
manipulate the environment.
The fish didn’t have anything else to do, so it
amused themselves by turning the light on. Unfortunately, I
didn’t follow up on the hypothesis (and neither did Longo). Later, though, as
a graduate student at the University of Pennsylvania, my
interest in animal learning was revived by research showing
the importance of predictability and controllability in
classical and instrumental conditioning. Susan Mineka, a
fellow graduate student who later was to become a colleague
at Wisconsin and I applied these concepts to understanding
the phenomenon of “experimental neurosis” in animals (Mineka & Kihlstrom, 1978)
– still one of my all-time favorite papers.
[5]Unfortunately,
never
in print. But I
taught with McClelland at Harvard, and anyone who ever
worked with him was familiar with this formulation.
[6]
Tart’s edited volume was one of the first psychology books I
purchased that was not expressly for a course. It reprinted two
studies which had found interesting changes in EEG
activity during yoga and Zen meditation. As it happened,
that same year, Colgate hosted Shibayama Roshi,
chief abbot of the Nanzen-ji monastery in Kyoto, who gave
a seminar on Zen Buddhism. Here was this Zen master; Edmonston had a
polygraph, and I was determined to put electrodes on him
while he meditated. Shibayama
was staying at Chapel House on campus, and I was invited
to a group dinner with him through Polly Adler, the
resident manager, whom I knew through church. During the
dinner I brought up the articles, and Shibayama expressed
interest. Yes! In a later
interview, I described the findings further: Zen
meditators didn’t show habituation of the “alpha blocking”
orienting response to novel stimuli. They treated
each repetition as if the stimulus had never occurred
before. This
seemed to be in line with the Zen goal of treating every
object and experience as if it were novel thing in and of
itself, not a member of a familiar category. Shibayama’s
response was "It's very interesting, but what does it
mean?" “It provides scientific validation of what
the meditators are doing,” I replied. “But we already
know that!” I
asked if he would allow me to record his EEG while he
meditated. "If the Pope were here, would you ask to
record his brainwaves while he prayed?". “No.” “Why not?” I had no answer,
and the interview ended.
In The Laughing Buddha of Tofukuji, Ishwar
Harris reports that, at one point, Shibayama told his
student Fukushima (Gensho) that he should return to his
university, "implying that Gensho thought like a scholar
not like a koan
student". Perhaps Shibayama was offering me similar
advice. But in retrospect, I think that his
questions were my own little Zen koan -- and that
when I solved it, I would be at least a little bit closer
to enlightenment.